scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Author

Gaisi Takeuti

Bio: Gaisi Takeuti is an academic researcher from University of Illinois at Urbana–Champaign. The author has contributed to research in topics: Set theory & Bounded function. The author has an hindex of 18, co-authored 60 publications receiving 1595 citations.


Papers
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: From a logical standpoint, each logic has its corresponding set theory in which each logical operation is translated into a basic operation for set theory; namely, the relation ⊆ and = on sets are translation of the logical operations → and ↔.
Abstract: In 1965 Zadeh introduced the concept of fuzzy sets. The characteristic of fuzzy sets is that the range of truth value of the membership relation is the closed interval [0, 1] of real numbers. The logical operations ⊃, ∼ on [0, 1] which are used for Zadeh's fuzzy sets seem to be Łukasiewciz's logic, where p ⊃ q = min(1, 1 − p + q), ∼ p = 1 − p. L. S. Hay extended in [4] Łukasiewicz's logic to a predicate logic and proved its weak completeness theorem: if P is valid then P + Pn is provable for each positive integer n. She also showed that one can without losing consistency obtain completeness of the system by use of additional infinitary rule.Now, from a logical standpoint, each logic has its corresponding set theory in which each logical operation is translated into a basic operation for set theory; namely, the relation ⊆ and = on sets are translation of the logical operations → and ↔. For Łukasiewicz's logic, P Λ (P ⊃ Q). ⊃ Q is not valid. Translating it to the set version, it follows that the axiom of extensionality does not hold. Thus this very basic principle of set theory is not valid in the corresponding set theory.

265 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The main tool is a Herbrand-type witnessing theorem for ∃∀∃Пbi-formulas provable in Ti2 where the witnessing functions are □pi+1.

156 citations

Book
21 Aug 1978

156 citations

Book ChapterDOI
01 Jan 1981
TL;DR: This paper studies set theory based on quantum logic, which is the lattice of all closed linear subspaces of a Hilbert space and shows the fact that there are many complete Boolean algebras inside quantum logic.
Abstract: In this paper, we study set theory based on quantum logic. By quantum logic, we mean the lattice of all closed linear subspaces of a Hilbert space. Since quantum logic is an intrinsic logic, i.e. the logic of the quantum world, (cf. 1) it is an important problem to develop mathematics based on quantum logic, more specifically set theory based on quantum logic. It is also a challenging problem for logicians since quantum logic is drastically different from the classical logic or the intuitionistic logic and consequently mathematics based on quantum logic is extremely difficult. On the other hand, mathematics based on quantum logic has a very rich mathematical content. This is clearly shown by the fact that there are many complete Boolean algebras inside quantum logic. For each complete Boolean algebra B, mathematics based on B has been shown by our work on Boolean valued analysis 4, 5, 6 to have rich mathematical meaning. Since mathematics based on B can be considered as a sub-theory of mathematics based on quantum logic, there is no doubt about the fact that mathematics based on quantum logic is very rich. The situation seems to be the following. Mathematics based on quantum logic is too gigantic to see through clearly.

93 citations


Cited by
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors propose a method to solve the problem of homonymity in homonymization, i.e., homonym-of-subjects-with-objectivity.
Abstract: ion

1,268 citations

Book ChapterDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors emphasized the fundamental principle that the expected value of an n-dimensional vector valued random variable is a probability measure defined on euclidean n-space E n.
Abstract: To explain the idea behind the present paper the following fundamental principle is emphasized. Let X = (X 1,…, X n ) be an n-dimensional vector valued random variable, and let µ(x) =µ(x 1…, x n )be its probability measure (defined on euclidean n-space E n ). Suppose that X has the property that µ(x) =µ(gx) for every element g of a group G of order h of transformations of E n into itself. Let f(x) =f(x 1…, x n ) be a µ-integrable complex valued function on E n Then the expected value of f(x) is $$Ef\left( X \right) = \smallint f\left( x \right)d\mu \left( x \right) = \smallint \bar f\left( x \right)d\mu \left( x \right)$$ (1.1) , where $$\bar f\left( x \right) = \frac{1}{h}\sum\limits_{g \in G} f \left( {gx} \right)$$ (1.2) .

656 citations

BookDOI
01 Jan 2002

548 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: A recursion-theoretic characterization of FP which describes polynomial time computation independently of any externally imposed resource bounds, and avoids the explicit size bounds on recursion of Cobham.
Abstract: We give a recursion-theoretic characterization of FP which describes polynomial time computation independently of any externally imposed resource bounds. In particular, this syntactic characterization avoids the explicit size bounds on recursion (and the initial function 2|x|·|y|) of Cobham.

461 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This paper traces these models back to the underlying lattice that they are defined on, and keeps up with an important tradition of using algebraic structures for developing logical calculi and exposes in a clear manner the two models' formal equivalence.

401 citations