scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question

Showing papers by "Mieke Bal published in 2016"


01 Jan 2016
TL;DR: In this article, a psychoanalytic transfer of the katharsis effect on the recipient is proposed, which can be seen as an extension of the activity of reception it enhances.
Abstract: ion by which only a limited number of features of the model reappear. Hence, thirdly, the pleasure is in the (re?)construction of the model by means of signs, reversed by a detour via the recipient. This argument supports the view that the realism debate is irrelevant: if mimetic reception is a (re?)construction by the recipient of the semiosized model, the difference between figurative and nonfigurative art is negligible as far as the relation of art to reality is concerned, for in the case of an "emergency," the receiver just makes up a "model" if no existing one is available. I must admit that a few lines further on Aristotle seems to contradict himself when he argues that the pleasure is different if we do not recognize or know the model. Even then, however, two aspects of the same event are concerned, and in principle the difference is only relative. In both cases, though perhaps in different proportions, the pleasure of fre)connaissance and the pleasure caused by the form, the more specific aesthetic sign, or, in Lacanian terms, since we know that the signifier founds the signified, the difference between both aspects has lost its relevance. From the activity of the recipient thus formulated, it is only one step to the psychoanalytically important notion of katharsis. It is impossible to do justice to this concept so often discussed (for an example, see Verhoeff 1981) in the context of mimesis; what interests me here is the extension of the activity of reception it enhances. Katharsis is an aspect of mimesis in its effect on the recipient, which closes the circuit of the different but coexistent objects of mimesis. This influence, by a sort of psychoanalytical transfer of the katharsis onto the recipient, thus completes the relation between reality and art: reality-representation-reality (katharsis effectuated) 1 I 1 model copy of model copy of copy-new model for recipient DL deconstruct the concept of katharsis into three isotopes. The first one is in the context of a dialogue with Plato. For moral reasons, Plato was against mimesis because it was supposed to contaminate the recipient. Aristotle's notion of katharsis forms a binary opposition with this moral notion of contamination, and hence it can be located within the same moral isotope. The second isotope is in the psychoanalytical context. Aristotle names two disturbing emotions, phobos and eleos, fear and pity. These two emotions specify the possible emotive reactions of the recipient, according to the direction of identification. Fear is based on direct identification, while pity is based on a general feeling of justice that makes us feel sorrow if someone else is sufferingu'njustly. The common feature is malaise. This feature is in opposition to the aforementioned pleasure (hedone) of representation, which was merely a cognitive pleasure. The cognitive is thus opposed to the emotional, while the good (pleasure) is opposed to the bad (malaise). These four features cross in katharsis: the purification of (unconscious) bad feelings clears the way for the (conscious) knowing of good feelings, a process that elevates the cognitive to a higher level by the effect This content downloaded from 207.46.13.51 on Sun, 19 Jun 2016 06:09:41 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

9 citations



01 Jan 2016
TL;DR: The Predicament of Culture as discussed by the authors is a collection of essays on critical practice focusing on all sorts of cultural "texts" (exhibition catalogues, postcards, art collections, scholarly texts, and the very concepts we use to discuss all of these things).
Abstract: In James Clifford's (1988) book The Predicament of Culture, various essays on critical practice, focusing on all sorts of cultural "texts" (exhibition catalogues, postcards, art collections, scholarly texts, and the very concepts we use to discuss all of these things), demonstrate the difficulty of talking about meanings. Meanings shift constantly according to social and historical pressures. The predicament of culture, it appears, is the instability of the categories used to address it, to analyze it, even to live in it. It seems that the attempts made in various domains of cultural studies-notably, ethnography and anthropological theory-to reflect on the meaning of the language of domination out of which these domains emerged only lead to deeper dilemmas, to more troubling instances of self-doubt (see, e.g., Fabian 1983). If anywhere, it is in anthropology that the importance of meaning as a tool of power has been recognized and, subsequently, theorized and analyzed. The objects of Clifford's analysis constitute an ideal case for the importance of semiotics as a trans-, super-, or interdisciplinary theory. Although semiotics has largely been developed in conjunction with linguistics and literary analysis, thus almost inevitably giving language a position of theoretical privilege while simultaneously supporting the accusation that this very privileging is undue, in Clifford's work, semiotics confronts objects that are emphatically not linguistic-despite

1 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The dossier explores movement in four different meanings and their implications and places the contributions to the dossier in relation to them as mentioned in this paper, and examines how a few modernist figurative paintings display the primary features of the cinematic without resorting (only) to representing movement.
Abstract: The dossier explores movement in four different meanings and their implications. This introductory article lays out these topics and places the contributions to the dossier in relation to them. It starts with movement in the most obvious sense – the cinematic. I examine how a few modernist figurative paintings display the primary features of the cinematic without resorting (only) to representing movement. The second meaning of movement comes from the act of perception. According to Henri Bergson, perception is a selection by the perceiving subject and that subject’s memories. The third meaning of movement is affective. This is related to the synaesthetic nature of seeing, and the importance of especially tactility and hearing in it. The last meaning is the result of this: the potential to move us to action in the political domain.