scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question

Showing papers in "Synthese in 1994"


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Dec 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: This paper first presents, and then critically assess, a variety of recent anti-representationalist treatments, and suggests that so far, at least, the sceptical rhetoric outpaces both evidence and argument.
Abstract: Connectionism and classicism, it generally appears, have at least this much in common: both place some notion of internal representation at the heart of a scientific study of mind In recent years, however, a much more radical view has gained increasing popularity This view calls into question the commitment to internal representation itself More strikingly still, this new wave of anti-representationalism is rooted not in ‘armchair’ theorizing but in practical attempts to model and understand intelligent, adaptive behavior In this paper we first present, and then critically assess, a variety of recent anti-representationalist treatments We suggest that so far, at least, the sceptical rhetoric outpaces both evidence and argument Some probable causes of this premature scepticism are isolated Nonetheless, the anti-representationalist challenge is shown to be both important and progressive insofar as it forces us to see beyond the bare representational/non-representational dichotomy and to recognize instead a rich continuum of degrees and types of representationality

309 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: It is argued that, on the two main conceptions of explanation, IBE cannot be a foundational inference rule, and an account of IBE is sketched that makes it contextual and dependent on substantive empirical assumptions, much as simplicity seems to be.
Abstract: This paper discusses the nature and the status of inference to the best explanation (IBE). We (1) outline the foundational role given IBE by its defenders and the arguments of critics who deny it any place at all; (2) argue that, on the two main conceptions of explanation, IBE cannot be a foundational inference rule; (3) sketch an account of IBE that makes it contextual and dependent on substantive empirical assumptions, much as simplicity seems to be; (4) show how that account avoids the critics' complaints and leaves IBE an important role; and (5) sketch how our account can clarify debates over IBE in arguments for scientific realism.

97 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Oct 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: The theory of unification is refined in the light of so called “puzzling phenomena”, to enable important distinctions, such as that between consonant and dissonant understanding.
Abstract: The basic theory of scientific understanding presented in Sections 1–2 exploits three main ideas.First, that to understand a phenomenonP (for a given agent) is to be able to fitP into the cognitive background corpusC (of the agent).Second, that to fitP intoC is to connectP with parts ofC (via “arguments” in a very broad sense) such that the unification ofC increases.Third, that the cognitive changes involved in unification can be treated as sequences of shifts of phenomena inC. How the theory fits typical examples of understanding and how it excludes spurious unifications is explained in detail. Section 3 gives a formal description of the structure of cognitive corpuses which contain descriptive as well as inferential components. The theory of unification is then refined in the light of so called “puzzling phenomena”, to enable important distinctions, such as that between consonant and dissonant understanding. In Section 4, the refined theory is applied to several examples, among them a case study of the development of the atomic model. The final part contains a classification of kinds of understanding and a discussion of the relation between understanding and explanation.

89 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
Jon Elster1
01 Jan 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: L'A.
Abstract: L'A. considere que la rationalite (c'est-a-dire le choix reflechi de ce qui est le mieux), l'emotionalite et la normativite sociale sont les trois motivations essentielles de l'action humaine.Il se sert d'analyses de ces concepts pour etudier leurs rapports deux a deux, en particulier le couple emotion-raison qui le conduit a une analyse detaillee de la facon dont la vie emotionnelle elle-meme peut etre rationnelle ou irrationnelle

79 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Apr 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: Si les modeles inductiviste et hypothetico-deductiviste sont tous les deux limites dans leur presentation du rapport entre experience and theorie, une combinaison de deux saura peut-etre definir une solution pertinente aura lieu.
Abstract: Si les modeles inductiviste et hypothetico-deductiviste sont tous les deux limites dans leur presentation du rapport entre experience et theorie, une combinaison de deux saura peut-etre definir une solution pertinente. Etude du cas de la biologie evolutionniste

65 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Apr 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: Dans la pratique scientifique courante, la certitude est accordee aux principes de base d'une science mature et on dit que cette certitudes est fondee sur the preuve experimentale.
Abstract: Dans la pratique scientifique courante, la certitude est accordee aux principes de base d'une science mature et on dit que cette certitude est fondee sur la preuve experimentale. L'A. cherche a demontrer la facon dont deux formes interliees de l'inference, induction demonstrative et induction eliminative, peuvent etre utilisees en appui de jugements de ce type. Suit une illustration de leur application en discontinuite quantique au debut de ce siecle

57 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Sep 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: The rule of triadic interaction is shown to lead to the formation and preservation of unipolar and bipolar configurations of nations, with the strengths of relationships, both friendly and conflictual, intensifying through time.
Abstract: The evolution of internation relationships is studied by means of a mathematical model based on a popular rule of triadic interaction: “the friend of my friend is my friend, the friend of my enemy is my enemy, the enemy of my enemy is my friend, the enemy of my friend is my enemy”. The rule is shown to lead to the formation and preservation of unipolar and bipolar configurations of nations, with the strengths of relationships, both friendly and conflictual, intensifying through time. These results confirm speculations originally made in static, graph theoretic studies of the balancing of relationships within individuals, small groups and systems of nations.

39 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Dec 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: This work considers how a brain's (or a network's) being a dynamical system might be the key both to its realizing various essential features of cognition and also to a non-classical solution of (frame-type) problems plaguing classical cognitive science.
Abstract: David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (or a network's) being a dynamical system might be the key both to its realizing various essential features of cognition — productivity, systematicity, structure-sensitive processing, syntax — and also to a non-classical solution of (frame-type) problems plaguing classical cognitive science.

30 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Sep 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: The poliheuristic theory of decision-making is introduced as an alternative to the rational actor and cybernetic paradigms in international relations and delineates the mathematical formulations of the three decision- making models.
Abstract: There are presently two leading foreign policy decision-making paradigms in vogue. The first is based on the classical or rational model originally posited by von Neumann and Morgenstern to explain microeconomic decisions. The second is based on the cybernetic perspective whose groundwork was laid by Herbert Simon in his early research on bounded rationality. In this paper we introduce a third perspective — thepoliheuristic theory of decision-making — as an alternative to the rational actor and cybernetic paradigms in international relations. This theory is drawn in large part from research on heuristics done in experimental cognitive psychology. According to the poliheuristic theory, policy makers use poly (many) heuristics while focusing on a very narrow range of options and dimensions when making decisions. Among them, the political dimension is noncompensatory. The paper also delineates the mathematical formulations of the three decision-making models.

30 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: The aim of this paper is to make it clear how and why begging the question should be seen as a pragmatic fallacy which can only be properly evaluated in a context of dialogue.
Abstract: The aim of this paper is to make it clear how and why begging the question should be seen as a pragmatic fallacy which can only be properly evaluated in a context of dialogue. Included in the paper is a review of the contemporary literature on begging the question that shows the gradual emergence over the past twenty years or so of the dialectical conception of this fallacy. A second aim of the paper is to investigate a number of general problems raised by the pragmatic framework.

30 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Aug 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: I defend a version of color subjectivism — that colors are sortals for certain neural events — by arguing against a sophisticated form of color objectivism and by showing how a subjectivist can legitimately explain the phenomenal fact that colors seem to be properties of external objects.
Abstract: I defend a version of color subjectivism — that colors are sortals for certain neural events — by arguing against a sophisticated form of color objectivism and by showing how a subjectivist can legitimately explain the phenomenal fact that colors seem to be properties of external objects.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 May 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: A theory of idealisation in science is applied to Christopher Cherniak's arguments, resulting in a departure from traditional, formalist theories of rationality of a more radical kind than Cherniak contemplates, with widespread ramifications for philosophical theory, especially philosophy of science itself.
Abstract: In his bookMinimal Rationality (1986), Christopher Cherniak draws deep and widespread conclusions from our finitude, and not only for philosophy but also for a wide range of science as well. Cherniak's basic idea is that traditional philosophical theories of rationality represent idealisations that are inaccessible to finite rational agents. It is the purpose of this paper to apply a theory of idealisation in science to Cherniak's arguments. The heart of the theory is a distinction between idealisations that represent reversible, solely quantitative simplifications and those that represent irreversible, degenerate idealisations which collapse out essential theoretical structure. I argue that Cherniak's position is best understood as assigning the latter status to traditional rationality theories and that, so understood, his arguments may be illuminated, expanded, and certain common criticisms of them rebutted. The result, however, is a departure from traditional, formalist theories of rationality of a more radical kind than Cherniak contemplates, with widespread ramifications for philosophical theory, especially philosophy of science itself.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Dec 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: It is argued that ability in natural deduction itself may rely on pattern recognition abilities that enable us to operate on external symbols rather than encodings of rules that might be applied to internal representations.
Abstract: The relation between logic and thought has long been controversial, but has recently influenced theorizing about the nature of mental processes in cognitive science. One prominent tradition argues that to explain the systematicity of thought we must posit syntactically structured representations inside the cognitive system which can be operated upon by structure sensitive rules similar to those employed in systems of natural deduction. I have argued elsewhere that the systematicity of human thought might better be explained as resulting from the fact that we have learned natural languages which are themselves syntactically structured. According to this view, symbols of natural language are external to the cognitive processing system and what the cognitive system must learn to do is produce and comprehend such symbols. In this paper I pursue that idea by arguing that ability in natural deduction itself may rely on pattern recognition abilities that enable us to operate on external symbols rather than encodings of rules that might be applied to internal representations. To support this suggestion, I present a series of experiments with connectionist networks that have been trained to construct simple natural deductions in sentential logic. These networks not only succeed in reconstructing the derivations on which they have been trained, but in constructing new derivations that are only similar to the ones on which they have been trained.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: It is argued that van Fraassen's arguments for rejecting non-Bayesian rules is unsound, and that his voluntarism is subject to a fatal dilemma arising from the non-monotonic character of reasoning.
Abstract: Van Fraassen's epistemology is forged from two commitments, one to a type of Bayesianism and the other to what he terms voluntarism. Van Fraassen holds that if one is going to follow a rule in belief-revision, it must be a Bayesian rule, but that one does not need to follow a rule in order to be rational. It is argued that van Fraassen's arguments for rejecting non-Bayesian rules is unsound, and that his voluntarism is subject to a fatal dilemma arising from the non-monotonic character of reasoning.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 May 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: In this article, it is argued that existing axiomatic theories of utility do not provide the utility principle or the principle of maximising expected utility with a formal justification, and that these theories only put mild constraints on a decision-maker in a decision context.
Abstract: It is argued that existing axiomatic theories of utility do not provide the utility principle or the principle of maximising expected utility with a formal justification. It is also argued that these theories only put mild constraints on a decision-maker in a decision-context. Finally, it is argued that the prospects are not particularly bright for finding formal non-circular arguments for the utility principle that do not rely on the law of large numbers.

Journal ArticleDOI
Dag Prawitz1
01 Jan 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: Guide par cette question: comment connaissons-nous les significations?
Abstract: Guide par cette question: comment connaissons-nous les significations?, l'A. examine l'hypothese d'une theorie de la signification concue a partir de l'experience. Son propos le conduit a une analyse des theses quiniennes de l'inextricabilite du sens et de l'information (nous signifions ce que nous croyons), et de l'indetermination

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: This paper argues that, while classical logic can be formulated so as to satisfy a number of harmony constraints, the meanings of the standard logical constants cannot all be given by their introduction and/or elimination rules; negation, in particular, comes under close scrutiny.
Abstract: The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maintain, cannot be justified from this proof-theoretic perspective. This paper argues that, while classical logic can be formulated so as to satisfy a number of harmony constraints, the meanings of the standard logical constants cannot all be given by their introduction and/or elimination rules; negation, in particular, comes under close scrutiny.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Nov 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: It is shown that drastic measures are not necessary to make sense of macro-level causal relevance, for the case can be made by drawing on Paul Humphreys' recent work in ways suggested by the concrete examples considered here.
Abstract: By a macro-level feature, I understand any feature that supervenes on, and is thus realized in, lower-level features. Recent discussions by Kim have suggested that such features cannot be causally relevant insofar as they are not classically reducible to lower-level features. This seems to render macro-level features causally irrelevant. I defend the causal relevance of some such features. Such features have been thought causally relevant in many examples that have underpinned philosophical work on causality. Additionally, in certain typical biological cases, we conceive of causally relevant features at various compatible levels of analysis. When elaborated, these points make a strong prima facie case for macro-level causal relevance. However, we might abandon both the philosophical guideposts and the corresponding explanatory practice in the special sciences were we convinced that no reflective philosophical account could provide for the causal relevance there supposed. I show that such drastic measures are not necessary, for we can make sense of macro-level causal relevance by drawing on Paul Humphreys' recent work in ways suggested by the concrete examples considered here.

Book ChapterDOI
01 Nov 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: In this article, it is shown that if and only if R is relevant to a question Q, R is a reason, though not necessarily a complete or conclusive reason, for accepting or rejecting something as an answer to Q. Reasons of this kind are governed by appropriate covering laws or principled probabilities and a number of questions arise about the relationship between relevance and certain formal-logical properties.
Abstract: The classical analysis of relevance in probabilistic terms does not fit legal, moral or conversational relevance, and, though analysis in terms of a psychological model may fit conversational relevance, it certainly does not fit legal, moral or evidential relevance. It is important to notice here that some sentences are ambiguous between conversational and non-conversational relevance. But, if and only if R is relevant to a question Q, R is a reason, though not necessarily a complete or conclusive reason, for accepting or rejecting something as an answer to Q. Reasons of this kind are governed by appropriate covering laws or principled probabilities and a number of questions thus arise about the relationship between relevance and certain formal-logical properties.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Jan 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: L'article passe en revue les differentes orientations prises par la logique des quantificateurs, depuis Frege qui y voyait un langage universel pour la pensee and les mathematiques, proche du langage naturel.
Abstract: L'article passe en revue les differentes orientations prises par la logique des quantificateurs, depuis Frege qui y voyait un langage universel pour la pensee et les mathematiques, proche du langage naturel, et Peirce qui, a la meme epoque, y voyait surtout une possibilite de jeu purement formel. Les AA. se penchent en particulier sur l'evolution de ce langage, sur les rapports de la logique de premier ordre au principe de compositionalite, pour finalement conclure sur la relation entre le langage de la quantification et le langage naturel

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Sep 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: An incomplete information model of extended deterrence relationships is developed and it is found that an Extended Deterrence Game always has a unique Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium with a rather simple form.
Abstract: This paper develops an incomplete information model of extended deterrence relationships. It postulates players who are fully informed about the costs of war and all other relevant variables, save for the values their opponents place on the issues at stake, i.e., the pawn. We provide consistent and intuitively satisfying parallel definitions for two types of players, Hard and Soft, in terms of the parameters of our model. We also answer several particular questions about the strategy choices of players in an extended deterrence relationship and, by identifying all the Perfect Bayesian Equilibria of the game model we construct, specify typical behavior patterns. Our most general finding is that an Extended Deterrence Game always has a unique Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium with a rather simple form. A challenger initiates for certain if the pawn is valuable enough to it and never challenges otherwise, Likewise, a defender always resists if the pawn is valuable enough and never resists otherwise. In addition to identifying threshold values for optimal strategic choice, we provide existence conditions for the two distinct types of Perfect Bayesian Equilibria. This permits us to identify the exact set of conditions associated with bluffing strategies and to develop a theory of the necessary and sufficient conditions for extended deterrence crisis initiation and its resolution.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Oct 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: Hilbert's rare admission of a Kroneckerian influence does not constitute the basis of such a reconstruction; it is rather Kr onecker's mathematical practice which is seen as a forerunner of Hilbert's endeavour in the foundations of mathematics.
Abstract: Hilbert's programme is shown to have been inspired in part by what we can call Kronecker's programme in the foundations of an arithmetic theory of algebraic quantities.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Dec 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: If connectionist are to meet the challenge, they are going to have to insist on the propriety of changing what counts as an explanation of systematicity, and there would seem to be as yet no reason to suppose that connectionists are unable to explain systematicity.
Abstract: Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988), Fodor and McLaughlin (1990) and McLaughlin (1993) challenge connectionists to explain systematicity without simply implementing a classical architecture. In this paper I argue that what makes the challenge difficult for connectionists to meet has less to do with what is to be explained than with what is to count as an explanation. Fodor et al. are prepared to admit as explanatory, accounts of a sort that only classical models can provide. If connectionists are to meet the challenge, they are going to have to insist on the propriety of changing what counts as an explanation of systematicity. Once that is done, there would seem to be as yet no reason to suppose that connectionists are unable to explain systematicity.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Dec 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: The present paper argues that the Syntactic Argument can be made to show that RWR is inconsistent with connectionism, and claims that the node-level rules of connectionist networks serve to determine a set of representation- level rules incompatible with the RWR conception of cognition.
Abstract: Terry Horgan and John Tienson have suggested that connectionism might provide a framework within which to articulate a theory of cognition according to which there are mental representations without rules (RWR) (Horgan and Tienson 1988, 1989, 1991, 1992). In essence, RWR states that cognition involves representations in a language of thought, but that these representations are not manipulated by the sort of rules that have traditionally been posited. In the development of RWR, Horgan and Tienson attempt to forestall a particular line of criticism, theSyntactic Argument, which would show RWR to be inconsistent with connectionism. In essence, the argument claims that the node-level rules of connectionist networks, along with the semantic interpretations assigned to patterns of activation, serve to determine a set of representation-level rules incompatible with the RWR conception of cognition. The present paper argues that the Syntactic Argument can be made to show that RWR is inconsistent with connectionism.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Nov 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: An outline of a metaphysical conception of modern science is presented in which a fundamental distinction is drawn between scientific principles, laws and theories, and a dimension is added to the analysis ofmodern science which allows for a more realistic account of its nature.
Abstract: In this paper an outline of a metaphysical conception of modern science is presented in which a fundamental distinction is drawn between scientific principles, laws and theories. On this view, ontologicalprinciples, rather than e.g. empirical data, constitute the core of science. The most fundamental of these principles are three in number, being, more particularly (A) the principle of the uniformity of nature, (B) the principle of the perpetuity of substance, and (C) the principle of causality. These three principles set basic constraints on the methodology of both empirical and theoretical science. The uniformity principle is central to the empirical aspect of science, suggesting a methodology consisting in the attempt to discover empiricallaws, while the causality principle is central to the theoretical aspect of science, suggesting the postulation of scientifictheories capable of indicating the causal basis of the laws. And the perpetuity principle functions so as to form a bridge between the theories and the laws. By distinguishing between principles, laws and theories in this way, a dimension is added to the analysis of modern science which allows for a more realistic account of its nature.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Dec 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: It is argued that the currently available evidence fails to support any of the three comparisons between classical architecture and connectionist architecture, and would offer some reason to think that cognitive architecture may be connectionist.
Abstract: There is currently a debate over whether cognitive architecture is classical or connectionist in nature. One finds the following three comparisons between classical architecture and connectionist architecture made in the pro-connectionist literature in this debate: (1) connectionist architecture is neurally plausible and classical architecture is not; (2) connectionist architecture is far better suited to model pattern recognition capacities than is classical architecture; and (3) connectionist architecture is far better suited to model the acquisition of pattern recognition capacities by learning than is classical architecture. If true, (1)–(3) would yield a compelling case against the view that cognitive architecture is classical, and would offer some reason to think that cognitive architecture may be connectionist. We first present the case for (1)–(3) in the very words of connectionist enthusiasts. We then argue that the currently available evidence fails to support any of (1)–(3).

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: It is claimed that a well-specified cognitive task is an empirical hypothesis about a system that involves the specification of input and output types and nomic correlations that underlie the system's performance.
Abstract: In this paper, I delineate two major problems facing reliabilist approaches in epistemology. I argue that Alvin Goodman's (1986) position fails to solve either problem. I then suggest an alternative reliabilist approach that ties truth-ratio assessments to particular, well-specified cognitive tasks. I claim that a well-specified cognitive task is an empirical hypothesis about a system that involves the specification of input and output types and nomic correlations (including statistical correlations) that underlie the system's performance. On my approach, one characterizes processes by reference to the system's dispositions across the situations consistent with the task. Characterization is best understood as revealing a strategy or a set of strategies for generating outputs from inputs relying on certain nomic correlations associated with the task.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Apr 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: This paper attempts to make rational sense of the apparently circular procedure of Maxwell and Cavendish's inverse square law and to relate it to some variants of traditional problems concerning old and new evidence.
Abstract: Maxwell claimed that the electrostatic inverse square law could be deduced from Cavendish's spherical condenser experiment. This is true only if the accuracy claims made by Cavendish and Maxwell are ignored, for both used the inverse square law as a premise in their analyses of experimental accuracy. By so doing, they assumed the very law the accuracy of which the Cavendish experiment was supposed to test. This paper attempts to make rational sense of this apparently circular procedure and to relate it to some variants of traditional problems concerning old and new evidence.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Jan 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: The present task is to show how to write intentionality, so central in Husserl's philosophy, into Quine's system of ontological naturalism and naturalized epistemology or into Heidegger's account of human being and existential phenomenology.
Abstract: Is consciousness or the subject part of the natural world or the human world? Can we write intentionality, so central in Husserl's philosophy, into Quine's system of ontological naturalism and naturalized epistemology — or into Heidegger's account of human being and existential phenomenology? The present task is to show how to do so. Anomalous monism provides a key.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Mar 1994-Synthese
TL;DR: Liste des sources manuscrites des 1-188 des Investigations philosophiques de Wittgenstein qui devraient etre etudiees parallelement avec The Origin and Composition of Wittdenstein's Investigations.
Abstract: Liste des sources manuscrites des 1-188 des « Investigations philosophiques » de Wittgenstein » qui devraient etre etudiees parallelement avec « The Origin and Composition of Wittgenstein's Investigations « du professeur von Wright