scispace - formally typeset
Journal ArticleDOI

Coercion, Contract and the Limits of the Market

Kaushik Basu1
17 Jul 2007-Social Choice and Welfare (Springer-Verlag)-Vol. 29, Iss: 4, pp 559-579

...read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

CAE Working Paper #06-01
Coercion, Contract and the Limits of the Market
by
Kaushik Basu
January 2006
.

January 3, 2006
Coercion, Contract and the Limits of the Market
Kaushik Basu
Department of Economics
Cornell University
Ithaca, New York 14853
Email: kb40@cornell.edu
Abstract
It is a widely accepted principle of economics that if two or more adults
voluntarily agree to a contract or an exchange that has no negative fall-out on others, then
the government should not stop such a contract. This is often called the ‘principle of free
contract’ (PFC). There is a body of writing in economics which upholds the PFC. Yet,
this ubiquitous principle is ill-defined and full of ambiguities. For instance, since it refers
to voluntary choice, its proper use presumes an understanding of what is ‘voluntary’ and,
therefore, also, of what is coercive. What is ironic is that, while philosophers and legal
scholars have debated and analyzed these concepts and the validity of the principle of
free contract, there is very little discussion of these in economics, even though so much
of economics is founded on this principle. This has caused a lot of policy confusion. The
aim of this paper is to construct general rules for when we may violate the PFC. The
argument is constructed within the Paretian framework. Hence, the violation of the PFC
is not justified by appeal to deontological ethics or non-welfarist criteria. This is not an
easy task since the principle of free contract is often viewed as a rule that is a derivative
of the Pareto principle.
Key words: Coercion, voluntary choice, contracts, markets, government intervention.
Acknowledgements: This paper is based on my Colin Clark Lecture, 2004, held at the
Australasian Meetings of the Econometric Society, Melbourne, and a seminar
presentation at the Conference on the Philosophical Aspects of Social Choice Theory and
Welfare Economics, at the University of Caen, 20 June, 2005. The paper has existed in
the form of notes and sketches, but remained essentially unwritten till recently. Over this
time I have accumulated indebtedness to a large number of colleagues and friends. At the
certainty of omission, I would like to mention Geir Asheim, Abhijit Banerjee, Kuntal
Banerjee, Alaka Basu, Hyejin Ku, Wulf Gaertner, Prasanta Pattanaik, John Roemer,
Joshua Teitlebaum and Amartya Sen.

2
Coercion, Contract and the Limits of the Market
1. Principle of Free Contract
In 1995, soon after I moved to the U.S., I got a letter from a lawyer in California
requesting me to write a letter to a judge of the California Supreme Court in support of
his client. Not being sure of the ethics of such matters, let me not reveal names. His
client, Mr. X, had been approached by an entrepreneur, Mr. R, for a loan of $500,000 in
order to open a restaurant. They agreed to an annual interest rate of 12% and a schedule
of repayment in installments. For some time R paid him in accordance with the
repayment schedule; but then he began to default. After waiting for a while, X decided to
take R to court for breach of contract. The case was proceeding well and seemingly in
favor of X, when R’s lawyers discovered that a 12% interest rate was a violation of the
statutory limit on interest rates prevalent in California at that time, which set an upper
bound at 11% for interest rates on loans. This was used by R’s lawyers to argue that the
entire contract was null and void and, therefore, R should pay no interest; moreover, by
this argument, he had over paid X and so in fact ought to get money back from X.
It was at this stage that X’s lawyer decided to seek the support of some
economists (knowing, I suppose, our profession’s proclivity in such matters). What I
wrote to the Judge of the California Supreme Court was, in a nutshell, this. What the law
says has to be followed, but how severely a violation of the law has to be redressed often
depends on our view of how reasonable the law happens to be. And I went on to argue
that in this case the statutory interest law in California was quite unreasonable. When an
adult, especially someone who is business savvy, agrees to take a loan with a 12%
interest rate and another person agrees to lend money at 12% interest rate, presumably
both expect to be better off through this exchange. And if there is no reason to expect
this to have negative fall-outs on others, then no one should stop such a contract. Indeed,
the ability among adults to freely sign contracts and rely on them is the bedrock of a
vibrant, modern economy. Business, enterprise and progress are made possible by such

3
contracts and, equally, progress gets stymied if such contracts are disallowed. The rest of
what I wrote to the judge is not relevant here.
Some months later I met an economist who had received the same request from
the lawyer and had also written to the judge. On comparing notes we discovered that we
had taken almost exactly the same line. On consideration, this is not so surprising. It is a
widely accepted principle of economics that if two or more sentient adults voluntarily
agree to a contract or an exchange, which has no negative fall-out on those uninvolved in
the contract, then the government should not stop such a contract. This is often called the
‘principle of free contract’ (see Basu, 2003, for discussion) – PFC, in brief.
Though this paper will be concerned with the exceptions to this principle, I want
to stress its significance in enabling a market economy to function effectively. In the US
this principle is often viewed as protected by the Fourteenth Amendment (1868) to the
Constitution. The freedom of contract was often alluded to as a “property right” and there
are celebrated cases, such as Lochner v. the New York State, 1905, where any effort to
curtail work hours or legislatively raise wages was struck down by the courts as being in
violation of the freedom of individuals to sign contracts as they wished. Indeed, it is
arguable that one critical ingredient in the outstanding performance of the American
economy since the late nineteenth century is the faith the U.S. courts evinced in the
principle of free contract, even though, as we shall presently see, this is a principle that
can be overdone. There is a body of writing in economics which upholds the PFC (see,
eg., Friedman, 1962) and, more significantly, there is widespread, unwritten acceptance
of this principle
1
.
Despite the value of this principle, what is worrying is that its terms are, on
reflection, ill-defined and has its share of ambiguities. For instance, since it refers to
voluntary choice, its proper use presumes an understanding of what is ‘voluntary’ and,
therefore, also, of what is coercive. Yet these are concepts ill-understood in economics.
What is ironic is that, while philosophers and legal scholars have debated and analyzed
these concepts and the validity of the principle of free contract, there is very little
1
While economists typically value this principle as a critical instrument for economic progress and
efficiency, one can think of other, philosophical justifications for adhering to this principle, such as
equating a contract with a promise and maintaining, a priori, that it is immoral for promises to be broken
(see Kaplow and Shavell, 2002, Chapter 4, for discussion of some of these alternative justifications.)

4
discussion of these in economics, even though so much of economics is founded on this
principle.
This has caused a lot of policy confusion. On the one hand, we find wanton
violation of this principle by governments and bureaucrats. On a variety of matters
governments specify terms of contracts exogenously. In India, any firm that employs
over 50 laborers has pre-specified terms for laying-off workers spelled out in the
Industrial Dispute’s Act, 1947; and any firm employing more than 100 laborers has to
have prior permission from the government before it can lay off workers. A contract
voluntarily entered into by an entrepreneur and a worker that specifies terms of
disengagement which are different from what the law specifies (e.g. the salary will be
very high but the firm can ask the worker to quit with no prior notice and no severance
pay) will be dismissed by the courts as invalid in the same way that the loan contract in
California was considered null and void. So, if after having signed the contract, the
worker or the employer later reneges on it, the other side will not have any recourse to the
law. And knowing this, people in India do not typically sign such contracts. Many
economists have argued (and I find myself in agreement with them on this) that the
pervasive failure to respect the principle of free contract has harmed the Indian economy,
since entrepreneurs hesitate to start up businesses in which demand is volatile (for
instance, fashion garments) and require periodic hiring and laying off of workers.
There are mainstream economists and some legal scholars who take this line of
argument to an extremity, and do not recognize that the PFC can have any exceptions.
But it is not difficult to find examples where a majority would feel uncomfortable
adhering to the principle of free contract. Here are some examples.
In 1903 there was the celebrated case, The Port Caledonia and the Anna, in which
a vessel that got into a dangerous crisis at sea sought help from a tug (Wertheimer, 1996).
The master of the tug asked for £1,000 (an astronomical sum at that time) and made it a
‘take it or leave it’ offer. The master of the vessel, unsurprisingly, accepted the offer, but
later went to court. The court declared the ‘contract’ or agreement void and ruled that the
vessel master needed to pay £200. Evidently, the court’s ruling violated the PFC.
Second, suppose a firm puts up a sign outside the personnel office which makes it
clear to new workers that the firm pays its workers excellent salaries, gives generous


Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI

[...]

TL;DR: This article developed a conceptual framework with which to study contracting between small-holders and a commodity-processing firm and synthesize results from empirical studies of contract farming arrangements in five countries (Ghana, India, Madagascar, Mozambique, and Nicaragua).
Abstract: Summary Supermarkets, specialized wholesalers, processors, and agro-exporters are transforming the marketing channels into which smallholder farmers sell produce in low-income economies. We develop a conceptual framework with which to study contracting between smallholders and a commodity-processing firm. We then synthesize results from empirical studies of contract farming arrangements in five countries (Ghana, India, Madagascar, Mozambique, and Nicaragua). The resulting meta-narrative documents patterns of participation, the welfare gains associated with participation, reasons for nonparticipation, the significant extent of contract noncompliance, and the considerable dynamism of these value chains as farmers and firms enter and exit frequently.

486 citations

Journal ArticleDOI

[...]

TL;DR: In this paper, a vignette study on MTurk concerning participation in medical trials showed that a substantial minority of subjects concurred with the IRB's decision to disallow high incentives they deem coercive.
Abstract: IRBs can disallow high incentives they deem coercive. A vignette study on MTurk concerning participation in medical trials shows that a substantial minority of subjects concurs. They think...

46 citations

Journal ArticleDOI

[...]

TL;DR: In this paper, the authors developed a conceptual framework through which to study contracting between small-holder farmers and a commodity-processing firm and conducted an empirical meta-analysis of agricultural value chains in five countries across three continents (Ghana, India, Madagascar, Mozambique, and Nicaragua).
Abstract: Supermarkets, specialized wholesalers, and processors and agro-exporters’ agricultural value chains have begun to transform the marketing channels into which smallholder farmers sell produce in low-income economies We develop a conceptual framework through which to study contracting between smallholders and a commodity-processing firm We then conduct an empirical meta-analysis of agricultural value chains in five countries across three continents (Ghana, India, Madagascar, Mozambique, and Nicaragua) We document patterns of participation, the welfare gains associated with participation, reasons for non-participation, the significant extent of contract non-compliance, and the considerable dynamism of these value chains, as farmers and firms enter and exit frequently

45 citations

Journal ArticleDOI

[...]

TL;DR: In this paper, the authors present a simple theoretical model of conflict that defines a two-sector economy, where in a contested sector, two agents struggle to appropriate the maximum possible fraction of a contestable output and in an uncontested sector, they hold secure property rights over the production of some goods.
Abstract: This paper is intended to complement the existing literature on civil wars. First, it presents a simple theoretical model of conflict that defines a two‐sector economy. In a contested sector, two agents struggle to appropriate the maximum possible fraction of a contestable output. In an uncontested sector, they hold secure property rights over the production of some goods. Agents split their resource endowment between ‘butter’, ‘guns’ and ‘ice‐cream’. Following the theoretical insights the empirical analysis focuses on the relationship between civil wars and different sectors of the economy. In particular, a panel probit specification shows that the incidence of a civil war decreases in the size of manufacturing sector.

31 citations

Journal ArticleDOI

[...]

Kaushik Basu1
TL;DR: In this article, a Prisoner's Dilemma game among randomly picked individuals is used to show how our selfish rationality interacts with our innate sense of cooperation and how sub-groups of a society can form cooperative blocks, whether to simply do better for themselves or exploit others.
Abstract: Much of economics is built on the assumption that individuals are driven by self-interest and economic development is an outcome of the free play of such individuals. On the few occasions that the existence of altruism is recognized in economics, the tendency is to build this from the axiom of individual selfishness. The aim of this paper is to break from this tradition and to treat as a primitive that individuals are endowed with the ‘cooperative spirit’, which allows them to work in their collective interest, even when that may not be in their self-interest. The paper tracks the interface between altruism and group identity. By using the basic structure of a Prisoner's Dilemma game among randomly picked individuals and building into it assumptions of general or in-group altruism, the paper demonstrates how our selfish rationality interacts with our innate sense of cooperation. The model is used to outline circumstances under which cooperation will occur and circumstances where it will break down. The paper also studies how sub-groups of a society can form cooperative blocks, whether to simply do better for themselves or exploit others.

29 citations


References
More filters
Book

[...]

01 Jan 1962
TL;DR: In the classic bestseller, Capitalism and Freedom, Friedman presents his view of the proper role of competitive capitalism as both a device for achieving economic freedom and a necessary condition for political freedom as mentioned in this paper.
Abstract: In the classic bestseller, Capitalism and Freedom, Milton Friedman presents his view of the proper role of competitive capitalism--the organization of economic activity through private enterprise operating in a free market--as both a device for achieving economic freedom and a necessary condition for political freedom. Beginning with a discussion of principles of a liberal society, Friedman applies them to such constantly pressing problems as monetary policy, discrimination, education, income distribution, welfare, and poverty. "Milton Friedman is one of the nation's outstanding economists, distinguished for remarkable analytical powers and technical virtuosity. He is unfailingly enlightening, independent, courageous, penetrating, and above all, stimulating."-Henry Hazlitt, Newsweek "It is a rare professor who greatly alters the thinking of his professional colleagues. It's an even rarer one who helps transform the world. Friedman has done both."-Stephen Chapman, Chicago Tribune

7,019 citations

Book

[...]

01 Jan 1984
TL;DR: In this paper, the author claims that we have a false view of our own nature and that it is often rational to act against our own best interests, that most of us have moral views that are directly self-defeating, and that when we consider future generations the conclusions will often be disturbing.
Abstract: This book challenges, with several powerful arguments, some of our deepest beliefs about rationality, morality, and personal identity. The author claims that we have a false view of our own nature; that it is often rational to act against our own best interests; that most of us have moral views that are directly self-defeating; and that, when we consider future generations the conclusions will often be disturbing. He concludes that non-religious moral philosophy is a young subject, with a promising but unpredictable future.

4,517 citations

Book

[...]

01 Jan 1970
TL;DR: The second edition of Collective Choice and Social Welfare as discussed by the authors was published in 1970 and has been widely used in the social choice literature since its early 1970s, and is considered a classic work in social choice.
Abstract: Nobel Prize winner Amartya Sen's first great book, now reissued in a fully revised and expanded second edition 'Can the values which individual members of society attach to different alternatives be aggregated into values for society as a whole, in a way that is both fair and theoretically sound? Is the majority principle a workable rule for making decisions? How should income inequality be measured? When and how can we compare the distribution of welfare in different societies?' These questions, from the citation by the Swedish Academy of Sciences when Amartya Sen was awarded the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics, refer to his work in Collective Choice and Social Welfare, the most important of all his early books. Originally published in 1970, this classic work in welfare economics has been recognized for its ground-breaking role in integrating economics and ethics, and for its influence in opening up new areas of research in social choice, including aggregative assessment. It has also had a large influence on international organizations, including the United Nations, particularly in its work on human development. In its original version, the book showed that the 'impossibility theorems' in social choice theory-led by the pioneering work of Kenneth Arrow-need not be seen as destructive of the possibility of reasoned and democratic social choice. Sen's ideas about social choice, welfare economics, inequality, poverty and human rights have continued to evolve since the book's first appearance. This expanded edition, which begins by reproducing the 1970 edition in its entirety, goes on to present eleven new chapters of new arguments and results. As in the original version, the new chapters alternate between non-mathematical chapters completely accessible to all, and those which present mathematical arguments and proofs. The reader who prefers to shun mathematics can follow all the non-mathematical chapters on their own, to receive a full, informal understanding. There is also a substantial new introduction which gives a superb overview of the whole subject of social choice.

3,042 citations

Book

[...]

01 Jan 1973
TL;DR: In this paper, Amartya Sen relates the theory of welfare economics to the study of economic inequality and presents a systematic treatment of the conceptual framework as well as the practical problems of measurement of inequality.
Abstract: In this classic text, first published in 1973, Amartya Sen relates the theory of welfare economics to the study of economic inequality. He presents a systematic treatment of the conceptual framework as well as the practical problems of measurement of inequality. In his masterful analysis, Sen assesses various approaches to measuring inequality and delineates the causes and effects of economic disparities. Containing the four lectures from the original edition as well as a new introduction, this timeless study is essential reading for economists, philosophers, and social scientists. In a new introduction, Amartya Sen, jointly with James Foster, critically surveys the literature that followed the publication of this book, and also evaluates the main analytical issues in the appraisal of economic inequality and poverty.

2,825 citations

Journal ArticleDOI

[...]

TL;DR: In this article, the authors present an impossibility result that seems to have some disturbing consequences for principles of social choice, and formalize this concept of individual liberty in an extremely weak form and examine its consequences.
Abstract: The purpose of this paper is to present an impossibility result that seems to have some disturbing consequences for principles of social choice. A common objection to the method of majority decision is that it is illiberal. The argument takes the following form: Given other things in the society, if you prefer to have pink walls rather than white, then society should permit you to have this, even if a majority of the community would like to see your walls white. Similarly, whether you should sleep on your back or on your belly is a matter in which the society should permit you absolute freedom, even if a majority of the community is nosey enough to feel that you must sleep on your back. We formalize this concept of individual liberty in an extremely weak form and examine its consequences.

1,053 citations



Frequently Asked Questions (1)
Q1. What are the contributions in "Coercion, contract and the limits of the market" ?

The aim of this paper is to construct general rules for when the authors may violate the PFC.