scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal ArticleDOI

Embracing ontological doubt: The role of ‘reality’ in political realism:

01 Feb 2017-Journal of International Political Theory (SAGE Publications)-Vol. 13, Iss: 1, pp 59-80
TL;DR: In this article, the authors argue that classical realism is conspicuously similar to critical international relations, but they do not challenge the observation that both approaches are comparable when it comes to ethical concerns and a related critique of modernity.
Abstract: While a number of scholars argue that classical realism is conspicuously similar to critical international relations, this article takes an issue with such an interpretation. It does not challenge the observation that both approaches are comparable when it comes to ethical concerns and a related critique of modernity, but it puts forth an argument that they differ fundamentally when it comes to their basic intellectual motivation and purpose. This also makes classical realism more ready to formulate normative judgment. To articulate what provides for the ethical impetus in classical realism, the study turns to the work of Stephen Turner and his collaborators who illuminate Weberian sources of classical realist social science. Adopting the category of analyticism from Patrick Jackson, it further puts forth that normative judgment is linked to classical realism’s inherent ontological doubt, a feature it compensates for by focusing on epistemology necessitating constant engagement with empirical reality as a...

Summary (1 min read)

2. The science of classical realism

  • Political realism at one point dominated IR because of its scientific advancement.
  • He does so by exploring the works of realist thinkers through the prism of what he calls 'the tragic vision', which should 'widen [the] intellectual and emotional horizons in a manner conducive to political tolerance and reconciliation' (24).

3. Embracing ontological doubt

  • Classical realist Weberian IR enables understanding of singular phenomena.
  • They helpfully point out that the ideal-type upon which Morgenthau developed his theory 'was linked to a specific historical situation and role, that of the politician and diplomat concerned with national interest ' (495) .
  • A political theorist sceptical about philosophical foundationalism, Shklar turns to socially produced knowledge to provide crucial orientation for her normatively oriented political theory.
  • Runciman continuously invites the figure of a hypothetical 'rival observer' to question whether a report is not 'inaccurate' or does not 'involve a misunderstanding'.
  • At the same time, Shklar is instructive on how knowledge rooted in ontological doubt can have normative validity, as this is precisely what she examines.

Conclusion

  • Applying Jackson's characteristics to critical IR and classical realism , the authors may conclude that what differentiates the two is disagreement about the possibility to 'transcend experience', a belief that there is a 'possibility of going beyond the facts to grasp the deeper processes and factors that generate those facts' (Jackson, 2011: 36-7) .
  • While never fully objective, the faculty of judgment employed at all stages of scientific inquiry is the best tool to be had.
  • While sharing a great deal, classical realism differs from critical IR precisely on the issue of ontological doubt and the role scientific engagement with empirical reality has in addressing this doubt.
  • Levine (2013) is right; Morgenthau was not a critical theorist.

Did you find this useful? Give us your feedback

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Aberystwyth University
Embracing Ontological Doubt
Stullerova, Kamila
Published in:
Journal of International Political Theory
DOI:
10.1177/1755088216673079
Publication date:
2017
Citation for published version (APA):
Stullerova, K. (2017). Embracing Ontological Doubt: The Role of ‘Reality’ in Political Realism. Journal of
International Political Theory, 13(1), 59-80. https://doi.org/10.1177/1755088216673079
General rights
Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Aberystwyth Research Portal (the Institutional Repository) are
retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the
legal requirements associated with these rights.
• Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the Aberystwyth Research Portal for the purpose of private study or
research.
• You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain
• You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the Aberystwyth Research Portal
Take down policy
If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately
and investigate your claim.
tel: +44 1970 62 2400
email: is@aber.ac.uk
Download date: 09. Aug. 2022

1
Embracing Ontological Doubt: The Role of ‘Reality’ in Political Realism
by Kamila Stullerova
Department of International Politics, Aberystwyth University, Aberystwyth SY23 3FE, UK.
Email: kas@aber.ac.uk
This is a pre-publication draft copy intended for green open access. The articles final version
is published in the Journal of International Political Theory, October 19, 2016:
http://ipt.sagepub.com/content/early/2016/10/18/1755088216673079.full.pdf+html
doi: 10.1177/1755088216673079
Abstract
While a number of scholars argue that classical realism is conspicuously similar to critical
international relations, this article takes an issue with such an interpretation. It does not
challenge the observation that both approaches are comparable when it comes to ethical
concerns and a related critique of modernity, but it puts forth an argument that they differ
fundamentally when it comes to their basic intellectual motivation and purpose. This also
makes classical realism more ready to formulate normative judgment. To articulate what
provides for the ethical impetus in classical realism, the study turns to the work of Stephen
Turner and his collaborators who illuminate Weberian sources of classical realist social
science. Adopting the category of analyticism from Patrick Jackson, it further puts forth that
normative judgment is linked to classical realism’s inherent ontological doubt, a feature it
compensates for by focusing on epistemology necessitating constant engagement with
empirical reality as a source of its (weak) ontological orientation. As a result, classical realism
is reinforced here as an approach to international relations worth reviving and further
developing.
Keywords
Classical Realism, Hans J Morgenthau, Critical IR, Max Weber, social science, normative
judgment
Embracing Ontological Doubt: The Role of ‘Reality’ in Political Realism
The social scientist is a part of history from which his knowledge is constructed;
every tomorrow, that knowledge may have to be revised or abandoned altogether.
WG Runciman (1963: 174)
Introduction
1
The number of works revisiting IR’s classical realism which have appeared in the last dozen
or so years is large enough to divulge that the once deprecated approach resonates with
intellectual needs and quests of current IR scholarship. What exactly are the gaps that
classical realism helps to fill in has so far not been systematically examined, although there is
a number of partial accounts along these lines. Classical realism lends new energy and a
particular direction to the theorising of the ethics of responsibility (Williams, 2005; Lebow,
1
The article was produced as part of the Leverhulme Trust funded project ‘Classical Realism Meets Critical
Theory’ and its earlier versions were presented at the project’s workshops in Newcastle (2013) and Ottawa
(2014). I am grateful for the generous input of the project’s members into the making of this article and for
additional editorial comments from Hartmut Behr and Michael Williams.

2
2003), the virtue of reflexivity (Lebow, 2003), ethical leadership (Tjalve, 2008) or the need of
a fundamental transformation of the state (Craig, 2003; Scheuerman, 2011). As can be seen
already from this brief outline of its key themes, in its sensibilities, the revival of classical
realism is conspicuously close to critical IR. It is, therefore, crucial to ask whether the
classical realist revival is a part or a new stage of the critical turn in IR, which is both older
and more robust than is the present turn to classical realism.
Two issues may prevent us from reaching such a conclusion. First, it is the question of
normative judgment. The promise of normative judgment seems to be stronger in classical
realism than it is in critical IR, which is suspicious of normativity’s universalism. If classical
realism is a version of critical IR, it must come to terms with the latter’s unease about
normativity. Second, the renewed interest in the works of classical realists has not yet
produced new research into contemporary international politics which would utilise classical
realist theory.
2
Unless such research is produced, one may ask whether the revival of classical
realism is anything more than an antiquarian quest to engage past, oft-forgotten works of one-
time giants of our field, which as is usually the case lends a new perspective on what we
are already set to do, strengthening our vision but without fundamentally challenging the way
we do research. This article argues that the two points are crucially intertwined. By asking
about the reluctance to produce new classical realist research in international relations, we
may be able to answer the question how, if at all, classical realism is distinct from critical IR
and where it grounds its commitment to normative judgment.
Several commentators on the current revival of classical realism point out a striking similarity
between the critical sensibilities of the key protagonists of this revival and the critical
tradition in IR (Steele, 2007; Cozette, 2008a, 2008b; Hom and Steele, 2010).
3
Some argue
that it is the engagement with the work of classical realists as nurtured by contemporary
critical sensibilities that produces what they call reflexive realism (Steele, 2007); others locate
the very critical sensibilities in classical realism itself (Scheuerman, 2008). At the same time,
there is also a growing unease with the idea that Morgenthau et al. should be seen as
precursors of the critical turn in IR or even as critical IR theorists themselves. Daniel Levine
(2013) makes a compelling argument why Morgenthau should not deemed a critical theorist.
Compared to Frankfurt School’s anti-foundationalism, Morgenthau comes across as
‘profoundly epistemologically and ontologically conservative’ (Levine, 2013: 96). Yet, we
must ask whether admirers and critics alike assess classical realism on its own terms. After
all, classical realism fell out of fashion and ceased shaping our scholarly receptiveness. It
might well be that IR’s current the critical sensibilities as well as expectations on what is good
scholarship are preventing us from recognising classical realism’s unique character and,
concomitantly, from making full use of its own scholarly potential.
Starting with the established premise that mid-century (now classical’) realism lost to its
competitors on the grounds of its alleged scientific inadequacies (Waltz, 1959; Gilpin, 1984;
Vasquez, 1998: 41), the article’s first section examines the role of social science in both
critical IR and classical realism. Within the context of this study, science is understood in
Patrick Jackson’s (2011) pluralist sense, as a systematic inquiry to produce factual knowledge
about the empirical world of international relations. The opening section emphasises the
tendency in critical IR to neglect scientific inquiry, arguing that classical realism does not
2
Rathbun (2008) illustrates why neoclassical realism cannot be seen as fulfilling this role.
3
For the purpose of this article, I understand the critical IR tradition broadly, including scholarship inspired by
Frankfurt School Critical Theory, approaches developed out of the Coxian reading of Horkheimer as well as
post-structuralist scholarship.

3
have a comparable option of resorting to philosophy. While present scholarship has
appreciated the specificity of classical realist take on social science, this has not been a key
research area. This relative neglect is understandable. In the 1950s and 60s classical realism
bitterly lost to the onslaught of behaviouralism, which triumphed as the more rigorous
approach. It thus comes as no surprise that scholars working on the rehabilitation of classical
realism have avoided repeating the mid-century battling. As a result, classical realism tends to
be understood and praised as a kind of international political theory, which is exactly what
its mid-century critics claimed it to be. To reverse this, the article turns its attention to
classical realist social sciences, exploring in its second section the thesis that it is a version or
precursor of IR constructivism before supporting the argument that it is best viewed as a
Weberian social science relying on ideal-types. The third section reinforces this interpretation
by exploring how Weberian social science necessitates cultivation of inner criticism as well as
the faculty of judgment which indicates when the inner critic is (temporarily) satisfied. It is
this faculty that informs the normative element of classical realism, one which looks
conspicuously close to critical IR’s cultivation of ethics, but is in fact nurtured from different
intellectual sources and practices of knowledge formation.
1. Classical realism and critical IR: Morgenthau is not Adorno
IRs critical turn in the 1980s and especially 90s was instigated from two directions:
scientific dissatisfaction with positivist IR that came to dominate the discipline and a longing
for an ethical dimension in scholarship. IR was to be made ethical in the sense that analysis,
its outcomes and the impact it is making on the social world was to be put under ethical
scrutiny. This was married with a re-kindled belief that, in one way or another, ideas can
produce a world better than the inherited one. Ensuing developments seem to have fulfilled
both needs. Critical IR responds to scientific critique of un-reflexive, rationalist positivism
and validates the ethical need by accounting for the power that knowledge brings about.
However, as already some of the earliest critics point out, critical IR is rarely capable of
satisfying its two intellectual roots the scientific and the ethical at the same time. Critical
IR’s resignation on furthering its scientific dimension cannot be replicated in classical
realism. Morgenthau, whom this study uses as an epitome of classical realism, was a social
scientist and an IR scholar, unlike the seminal figures of critical IR who were all philosophers
and often not particularly interested in international relations.
While directly focusing on only one segment of the wider category referred to here as critical
IR, Beate Jahn maintains that the Anglo-American strand of critical theory in IR sees ‘the
epistemological critique of the fact-value relationship not as a basis for a more rigorous
methodological approach than positivism, but rather as a licence of not observing any kind of
rigour’ (1998: 614). According to Jahn, critical IR is complacent about honing its own
scientific credentials. Instead, it seeks to build bridges between various theories and
incorporates ‘valuable parts’ of realism, rationalism and idealism in areas it cannot provide
for with its own theoretical means (1998: 626). Jahn worries that methodological laxity
cannot be counterbalanced by a noble ethical goal, joining here another critic, Josef Lapid
(1989).
Critical IR has not displayed any systematic engagement with challenges of this kind. Mark
Neufeld puts forth an argument why this is next to impossible (1995: 125). Critical IR seems
to have acted upon Neufeld’s point. Instead of investing energy into theorising critical social
science of international relations, it has placed extra effort into theorising its ethical
commitments and philosophical significance. For many critical IR scholars this translates into
non-normative cultivation of ethics, such as the ethics of scholarship as political action or the

4
ethics of responsibility, which do not make claims of normative universalism (Jabri, 1998;
Edkins, 1999, 2000; Dauphinée, 2007). Others embrace commitments to political norms and
related research interests (Linklater, 1998) but progressively do so in a rather abstract, though
no less vehement, manner which stops short of formulating a specific normative position on
current international affairs, focusing instead on long-term ethical orientation (Linklater,
2011). It should be added that this dual shift away from social science and towards ethics
might not have been propelled by only autochthonous forces. Most likely, it also happened as
a response to the hyper-scientism that came to dominate global IR, which did not leave much
space for alternatives as scientifically acceptable options. Toni Erskine is right to liken the
status quo of current IR to ‘trench warfare’ or, at best, see it as profound ‘indifference’
towards other approaches (2012: 449). Jackson’s quest (2011) to re-configure the parameters
of what is good scientific IR demolishes the trenches but, as will be shown later,
inadvertently reinforces critical IR’s reasons for turning away from its science.
Another strategy, present in critical IR from its very beginning, is to postulate that scientific
explanation is inherent to only some approaches those which critical IR rejects as
insufficient. Interestingly, Richard Ashley (1981) turns to John Herz and Hans Morgenthau to
introduce this point, a move that might also make him into a forerunner for the more recent
recovering of classical realism. Inspired by hermeneutics, Ashley distinguishes knowledge as
understanding and knowledge as explanation and postulates that not all IR must be concerned
with scientific explanation (1981: 212). In a sense, he celebrates the trenches Erskine
criticizes. The book Explaining and Understanding International Relations (Hollis and Smith,
1991) sealed Ashley’s thesis and in the eyes of many theorists brought the discussion about
the alleged scientific inadequacy of critical IR to a closure. As a result, critical IR’s
‘emancipatory interest’ (Ashley, 1981) and dedication to the politically excluded (George and
Campbell, 1990) has most forcefully shaped our present expectations on and our very idea of
what critical IR stands for.
In many ways, the revival of classical realism replicates the trajectory of critical IR. Emphasis
is placed on classical realism’s ethical commitments while scientific aspects are mostly
neglected; preference is given to in-depth interpretations of past thinkers over engagement
with contemporary theory and practice of international relations. The close attention paid to
Hans Morgenthau over the last dozen years (Lebow, 2003; Williams, 2005, 2007; Tjalve,
2008; Neacsu, 2009; Jütersonke, 2010; Scheuerman, 2013; Rösch, 2015) is not dissimilar to
the attention seminal philosophers have received within critical IR. Like critical IR, the
revival of classical realism highlights the problems of late modernity, especially ethical and
political consequences of global value neutrality in the face of differentiated histories, of
technological progress and environmental degradation. However, one factor in classical
realism prevents its revival from mimicking the route of critical IR. From its very beginning,
critical IR has been crucially nurtured by the philosophical works of Marx, Adorno,
Horkheimer, Habermas, Foucault, etc. That none of these primarily sought to explain
international relations has presented critical IR with a challenge which has been turned into an
opportunity. It allows critical IR to avoid confrontation with the wider discipline on the issue
of its science by constantly renewing its ethical orientation and critical diagnostics of the
maladies of the modern world in the robust philosophies which underpin it. This avenue is not
present for the revival of classical realism.
Jackson identifies ‘reflexivity as the chief characteristic of critical IR, meaning by it
‘reflexivity of knowledge, by which the tools of knowledge-production are turned back on the

Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In Carr's ethics, there is a link between the rise of the socialised nation and the crisis of laissez faire due to its loss of legitimacy among the lesser privileged.
Abstract: In Carr’s ethics, there is a link between the rise of the socialised nation and the crisis of laissez faire due to its loss of legitimacy among the lesser privileged. How far is this link in Carr’s...

14 citations


Cites background from "Embracing ontological doubt: The ro..."

  • ...Statists, for example, reject the framework of rights and obligations that is centred on the individual rather than the nations (Miller, 2007; Nagel, 2005; Walzer, 1983) and/or the peoples (Eckert, 2015; Rawls, 1999; Tong, 2017)....

    [...]

  • ...The implicit acceptance of the violence committed by the status quo under laissez faire can also be seen in the statist argument centred on the Rawlsian ‘peoples’ (Eckert, 2015; Rawls, 1999; Tong, 2017)....

    [...]

Dissertation
01 Jan 2019
TL;DR: In this article, the authors identify factors that influence collaborative environmental arrangements in Aotearoa-New Zealand and conduct a case study of Whakaraupō-Lyttelton Harbour.
Abstract: Enduring Traditions and Contested Authority: Collaborative Environmental Governance in Aotearoa-New Zealand. By Dion Charles Pue Luke The importance of natural resources to societal well being is revealed in the intense debate, contestation and conflict inherent in environmental management. Collaborative regimes are proferred as a means of integrating diverse environmental values and interests of local communities with state and non-state actors often excluding indigenous peoples. In Aotearoa-New Zealand, Treaty of Waitangi settlements and environmental legislation reform provide an increased opportunity for indigenous values to contribute to resource management decision making. Concurrently, central government industriously attempts to accommodate the requirements of multiple international agreements. This study attempts to identify factors that influence collaborative environmental arrangements in Aotearoa-New Zealand. Analysis of key domestic and international policy documents was undertaken, complemented by semi structured interviews conducted with recognised stakeholders for the case study area of Whakaraupō-Lyttelton Harbour. It is envisaged the study will clarify the roles policy diffusion, institutional capability and legal traditions play in environmental resource management for Aotearoa-New Zealand.

11 citations


Cites background from "Embracing ontological doubt: The ro..."

  • ...It also identifies which values would need to be activated to lead to the most preferred or ideal action (Stullerova, 2016)....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors examine the humanitarian approach to nuclear weapons, which has reinvigorated the efforts to achieve their prohibition, and explore the fundamental arguments made by the humanitarians.
Abstract: This article examines the humanitarian approach to nuclear weapons, which has reinvigorated the efforts to achieve their prohibition. It explores the fundamental arguments made by the ‘Humanitarian...

9 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, Herz is better known for his theorisation of the security dilemma than for his conviction that human survival is threatened by the conditions of late modernity, and he is the first to argue that the security of human survival may be jeopardized.
Abstract: John H. Herz (1908-2005) is better known for his theorisation of the security dilemma than for his conviction that human survival is threatened by the conditions of late modernity. This article exp...

5 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The renaissance of classical realism in International Relations (IR) has highlighted the close historical and conceptual connection between realism and liberalism as discussed by the authors. In this essay, we consider an alternative approach for realism and liberalism.
Abstract: The renaissance of classical realism in International Relations (IR) has highlighted the close historical and conceptual connection between realism and liberalism. In this essay, I consider an unde...

5 citations

References
More filters
Book
01 Jan 1972
TL;DR: In this paper, a theory of international politics, describes the struggle for political power, and discusses balance of power, international law, disarmament, and diplomacy. But this theory does not consider the role of women in international politics.
Abstract: Offers a theory of international politics, describes the struggle for political power, and discusses balance of power, international law, disarmament, and diplomacy.

3,179 citations

Book
01 Jan 1986
TL;DR: The sources of social power trace their interrelations throughout human history as discussed by the authors, from neolithic times, through ancient Near Eastern civilizations, the classical Mediterranean age and medieval Europe up to just before the Industrial Revolution in England.
Abstract: Distinguishing four sources of power in human societies – ideological, economic, military and political – The Sources of Social Power traces their interrelations throughout human history In this first volume, Michael Mann examines interrelations between these elements from neolithic times, through ancient Near Eastern civilizations, the classical Mediterranean age and medieval Europe, up to just before the Industrial Revolution in England It offers explanations of the emergence of the state and social stratification; of city-states, militaristic empires and the persistent interaction between them; of the world salvation religions; and of the particular dynamism of medieval and early modern Europe It ends by generalizing about the nature of overall social development, the varying forms of social cohesion and the role of classes and class struggle in history First published in 1986, this new edition of Volume 1 includes a new preface by the author examining the impact and legacy of the work

2,186 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
Ted Hopf1
TL;DR: A challenger to the continuing dominance of neorealism and neoliberal institutionalism in the study of international relations in the United States, constructivism is regarded with a great deal of skepticism by mainstream scholars as discussed by the authors.
Abstract: A challenger to the continuing dominance of neorealism and neoliberal institutionalism in the study of international relations in the United States, constructivism is regarded with a great deal of skepticism by mainstream scholars.1 While the reasons for this reception are many, three central ones are the mainstream's miscasting of constructivism as necessarily postmodern and antipositivist; constructivism's own ambivalence about whether it can buy into mainstream social science methods without sacrificing its theoretical distinctiveness; and, related to this ambivalence, constructivism's failure to advance an alternative research program. In this article, I clarify constructivism's claims, outline the differences between "conventional" and "critical" constructivism, and suggest a research agenda that both provides alternative understandings of mainstream interna-

1,134 citations


"Embracing ontological doubt: The ro..." refers background in this paper

  • ...Weber is not nowadays ordinarily understood as a key figure in IR, although some early IR constructivists refer to him as a ‘precursor’ to constructivism’s position on power (Hopf, 1998: 177)....

    [...]

Book
01 Jan 1959
Abstract: Foreword to the 2018 Anniversary Edition, by Stephen M. Walt Preface to the 2001 Edition Preface to the 1959 Edition 1. Introduction 2. The First Image: International Conflict and Human Behavior 3. Some Implications of the First Image: The Behavioral Sciences and the Reduction of Interstate Violence 4. The Second Image: International Conflict and the Internal Structure of States 5. Some Implications of the Second Image: International Socialism and the Coming of the First World War 6. The Third Image: International Conflict and International Anarchy 7. Some Implications of the Third Image: Examples from Economics, Politics, and History 8. Conclusion Bibliography Index

969 citations

Frequently Asked Questions (12)
Q1. What are the contributions mentioned in the paper "Embracing ontological doubt: the role of ‘reality’ in political realism" ?

While a number of scholars argue that classical realism is conspicuously similar to critical international relations, this article takes an issue with such an interpretation. To articulate what provides for the ethical impetus in classical realism, the study turns to the work of Stephen Turner and his collaborators who illuminate Weberian sources of classical realist social science. Adopting the category of analyticism from Patrick Jackson, it further puts forth that normative judgment is linked to classical realism ’ s inherent ontological doubt, a feature it compensates for by focusing on epistemology necessitating constant engagement with empirical reality as a source of its ( weak ) ontological orientation. As a result, classical realism is reinforced here as an approach to international relations worth reviving and further developing. 

Applying Jackson ’ s characteristics to critical IR ( reflexivity ) and classical realism ( analyticism ), the authors may conclude that what differentiates the two is disagreement about the possibility to ‘ transcend experience ’, a belief that there is a ‘ possibility of going beyond the facts to grasp the deeper processes and factors that generate those facts ’ As a result, classical realists do not worry about potential reification of meaning by the virtue of their inescapably limited, reductionist and what might be termed ‘ populist ’ idealtypes. But this does not mean he miscarried his own scientific and ethical aspirations, as Levine suggests. 

Critical IR responds to scientific critique of un-reflexive, rationalist positivism and validates the ethical need by accounting for the power that knowledge brings about. 

If one’s central intellectual concern is about the relationship of the self to knowledge, philosophy is the most rewarding intellectual home. 

The central notion of the ideal-type allows them to produce knowledge of the empirical world which has greater scientific validity than a simple aggregate of practitioners’ self-reporting utterances. 

Due to its purposeful ontological weakness, classical realism is not as easily translatable to present context as are some ontologically robust theories. 

IR’s critical turn in the 1980s and especially 90s was instigated from two directions: scientific dissatisfaction with positivist IR that came to dominate the discipline and a longing for an ethical dimension in scholarship. 

Because she is more attentive to normative knowledge than factual, Shklar locates ontological doubt as only a property of the realm of values (and fails to recognise its role also in the realm of facts). 

It is represented in the never-ending quest to make sense of empirical reality, which constantly escapes it, while also slowly appropriating the corrective meanings and normative interventions produced by realist scholarship in its intertwined but also separable scientific and normative modes. 

For instance, she champions human rights, the purpose of which is to judge and act in situations where there are signs of human suffering,without instantly necessitating a reliable reportage, description and evaluation of the situation. 

IR was to be made ethical in the sense that analysis, its outcomes and the impact it is making on the social world was to be put under ethical scrutiny. 

At the same time, Shklar is instructive on how knowledge rooted in ontological doubt can have normative validity, as this is precisely what she examines. 

Trending Questions (1)
What are some of the criticisms of classical realism?

The paper does not provide any specific criticisms of classical realism.