scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal Article•DOI•

Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference-Dependent Model

01 Nov 1991-Quarterly Journal of Economics (Oxford University Press)-Vol. 106, Iss: 4, pp 1039-1061
TL;DR: In this article, the authors present a reference-dependent theory of consumer choice, which explains such effects by a deformation of indifference curves about the reference point, in which losses and disadvantages have greater impact on preferences than gains and advantages.
Abstract: Much experimental evidence indicates that choice depends on the status quo or reference level: changes of reference point often lead to reversals of preference. We present a reference-dependent theory of consumer choice, which explains such effects by a deformation of indifference curves about the reference point. The central assumption of the theory is that losses and disadvantages have greater impact on preferences than gains and advantages. Implications of loss aversion for economic behavior are considered. The standard models of decision making assume that preferences do not depend on current assets. This assumption greatly simplifies the analysis of individual choice and the prediction of trades: indifference curves are drawn without reference to current holdings, and the Coase theorem asserts that, except for transaction costs, initial entitlements do not affect final allocations. The facts of the matter are more complex. There is substantial evidence that initial entitlements do matter and that the rate of exchange between goods can be quite different depending on which is acquired and which is given up, even in the absence of transaction costs or income effects. In accord with a psychological analysis of value, reference levels play a large role in determining preferences. In the present paper we review the evidence for this proposition and offer a theory that generalizes the standard model by introducing a reference state. The present analysis of riskless choice extends our treatment of choice under uncertainty [Kahneman and Tversky, 1979, 1984; Tversky and Kahneman, 1991], in which the outcomes of risky prospects are evaluated by a value function that has three essential characteristics. Reference dependence: the carriers of value are gains and losses defined relative to a reference point. Loss aversion: the function is steeper in the negative than in the positive domain; losses loom larger than corresponding gains. Diminishing sensitivity: the marginal value of both gains and losses decreases with their

Summary (2 min read)

I. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE

  • The examples discussed in this section are analyzed by reference to Figure II.
  • In every case the authors consider two options x andy that differ on two valued dimensions and show how the choice between them is affected by the reference point from which they are evaluated.
  • The common reason for these reversals of preference is that the relative weight of the differences between x and y on dimensions 1 and 2 varies with the location of the reference value on these attributes.
  • Diminishing sensitivity implies that the impact of a difference is attenuated when both options are remote from the reference point for the relevant dimension.

LOSSES GAINS FIGURE I

  • The entire body of evidence provides strong support for the phenomenon of loss aversion.
  • The sellers evaluate the same options from y; they must choose between retaining the status quo (the mug) or giving up the mug in exchange for money.
  • The results were analyzed by regressing the proportions of subjects choosing an option designated as status quo P(SQ), or an alternative to the status quo P(ASQ), on the choice proportions for the same options in the neutral version P (N).
  • As noted by Samuelson and Zeckhauser [19881, however, there are several factors, such as costs of thinking, transaction costs, and psychological commitment to prior choices that can induce a status quo bias even in the absence of loss aversion.
  • All subjects were informed that some of the winners, again selected at random, would be given an opportunity to exchange the original gift for one of the following options: x: two free dinners at MacArthur Park Restaurant y: one 8 x 10 professional photo portrait plus two 5 x 7 and three wallet size prints.

II. REFERENCE DEPENDENCE

  • The extension to more than two dimensions is straightforward.
  • Throughout this article the authors assume that each>.
  • Ye Under these assumptions each >r can be represented by a strictly increasing continuous utility function Ur (see, e.g., Varian [1984] , Ch. 3).
  • Next the authors introduce the notion of a decomposable reference function and characterize the concept of constant loss aversion.

Loss Aversion

  • The basic intuition concerning loss aversion is that losses (outcomes below the reference state) loom larger than corresponding gains (outcomes above the reference state).
  • Because a shift of reference can turn gains into losses and vice versa, it can give rise to reversals of preference, as implied by the following definition.
  • The present notion of loss aversion accounts for the endowment effect and the status quo bias described in the preceding section.
  • This explains the different valuations of a good by sellers and choosers and other manifestations of the status quo bias.

Diminishing Sensitivity

  • Recall that, according to the value function of Figure I, marginal value decreases with the distance from the reference point.
  • It is important to distinguish between the present notion of diminishing sensitivity, which pertains to the effect of the reference state, and the standard assumption of diminishing marginal utility.
  • Consider two exchangeable individuals (i.e., hedonic twins), each of whom holds position t, with low status and low pay; see.

Constant Loss Aversion

  • The present section introduces additional assumptions that constrain the relation among preference orders evaluated from different reference points.
  • The functions Ri are called the reference functions associated with reference state r.
  • It is easy to verify that reference interlocking follows from additive constant loss aversion.
  • The authors surmise that the coefficient of loss aversion associated with different dimensions reflects the importance or prominence of these dimensions [Tversky, Sattath, and Slovic, 1988].

III. IMPLICATIONS OF Loss AVERSION

  • Loss aversion is an important component of a phenomenon that has been much discussed in recent years: the large disparity often observed between the minimal amount that people are willing to accept (WTA) to give up a good they own and the maximal amount they would be willing to pay (WTP) to acquire it.
  • The buying-selling discrepancy was initially observed in hypothetical questions involving public goods (see Cummings, Brookshire, and Schulze [1986] , for a review), but it has also been confirmed in real exchanges [Heberlein and Bishop, 1985; Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler, 1990; Loewenstein, 1988] .
  • A trade involves two dimensions, and loss aversion may operate on one or both.
  • Questioning the values that decision makers assign to outcomes requires a criterion for the evaluation of preferences.
  • Because equality of R, differences implies equality of S, differences, Lemma 1 follows from continuity and additivity.

Did you find this useful? Give us your feedback

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference-Dependent Model
Author(s): Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman
Source:
The Quarterly Journal of Economics,
Vol. 106, No. 4 (Nov., 1991), pp. 1039-1061
Published by: Oxford University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2937956 .
Accessed: 26/04/2011 00:37
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Quarterly
Journal of Economics.
http://www.jstor.org

LOSS AVERSION IN
RISKLESS CHOICE:
A
REFERENCE-DEPENDENT MODEL*
AMos TVERSKY AND
DANIEL
KAHNEMAN
Much
experimental evidence indicates that
choice depends on the status quo or
reference level:
changes of reference point often
lead to reversals of preference. We
present
a
reference-dependent theory of consumer
choice, which explains such
effects
by a
deformation of indifference curves
about the reference point. The
central
assumption of the theory is that losses and
disadvantages have greater
impact on
preferences
than
gains
and
advantages.
Implications of loss aversion for
economic
behavior
are
considered.
The
standard models
of
decision
making assume that prefer-
ences
do
not
depend
on
current assets.
This assumption greatly
simplifies
the
analysis
of
individual choice
and
the
prediction
of
trades:
indifference
curves are
drawn without
reference
to
current
holdings, and the
Coase theorem asserts
that, except for transac-
tion
costs,
initial
entitlements
do not affect
final
allocations.
The
facts
of
the
matter are
more
complex.
There
is
substantial evidence
that
initial entitlements
do
matter and
that
the rate of exchange
between
goods
can
be quite different
depending
on
which is
acquired
and
which
is
given up,
even
in
the
absence
of
transaction
costs or
income
effects.
In
accord with a
psychological analysis
of
value,
reference levels play
a
large role
in
determining preferences.
In the present
paper we review the
evidence for this proposition
and offer a
theory
that
generalizes
the
standard model
by introduc-
ing a reference
state.
The
present analysis
of
riskless choice
extends
our
treatment
of
choice
under
uncertainty [Kahneman
and
Tversky, 1979, 1984;
Tversky
and
Kahneman, 1991], in which
the outcomes
of
risky
prospects
are
evaluated by
a
value function
that has three essential
characteristics.
Reference dependence:
the
carriers of
value are
gains
and
losses defined relative to a reference
point.
Loss
aversion:
the
function
is
steeper
in
the
negative
than
in
the
positive domain;
losses
loom
larger
than
corresponding
gains. Diminishing sensitiv-
ity:
the
marginal value
of
both
gains and
losses decreases with their
*This
paper has benefited from
the
comments of
Kenneth Arrow, Peter
Diamond,
David
Krantz,
Matthew
Rabin, and
Richard Zeckhauser. We are espe-
cially grateful
to
Shmuel
Sattath and
Peter
Wakker
for
their helpful suggestions.
This work
was
supported by
Grants
No. 89-0064
and
88-0206
from
the
Air
Force
Office of
Scientific
Research,
and
by
the Sloan
Foundation.
?
1991
by the President
and
Fellows
of
Harvard
College
and
the
Massachusetts Institute
of
Technology.
The
Quarterly Journal
of Economics, November
1991

1040
QUARTERLY
JOURNAL OF
ECONOMICS
size.
These
properties
give rise to an
asymmetric
S-shaped value
function,
concave above
the
reference point
and
convex
below it,
as
illustrated in
Figure
I.
In this
article
we apply
reference
dependence, loss
aversion,
and
diminishing
sensitivity
to the
analysis
of
riskless
choice.
To
motivate
this
analysis,
we
begin with a
review
of
selected
experimen-
tal
demonstrations.
I.
EMPIRICAL
EVIDENCE
The
examples
discussed in
this
section are
analyzed
by refer-
ence
to
Figure
II.
In
every
case
we
consider two
options
x
andy
that
differ
on
two valued
dimensions and show how
the
choice between
them is
affected
by
the
reference
point
from which
they
are
evaluated. The common
reason
for
these
reversals
of
preference
is
that the
relative
weight
of the
differences between x
and
y
on
dimensions
1
and 2
varies with the location of
the
reference value
on these
attributes.
Loss
aversion
implies
that the
impact
of a
difference on
a
dimension
is
generally greater
when
that
difference
is
evaluated
as a loss than
when
the same
difference is
evaluated
as
a
gain.
Diminishing
sensitivity implies
that the
impact
of
a
difference
is attenuated when both
options
are remote from
the
reference point for the
relevant
dimension. This
simple scheme
VALUE
LOSSES
GAINS
FIGURE
I
An
Illustration of
a
Value
Function

LOSS
AVERSION IN
RISKLESS
CHOICE
1041
serves
to
organize
a
large
set of
observations.
Although
isolated
findings
may be subject to
alternative
interpretations,
the
entire
body of
evidence provides
strong
support
for
the phenomenon of
loss aversion.
a. Instant
Endowment. An
immediate
consequence
of
loss
aversion is that
the loss
of
utility associated with
giving up
a
valued
good
is
greater than the
utility gain associated with
receiving
it.
Thaler
[1980]
labeled this
discrepancy the
endowment
effect,
because
value
appears
to
change when a
good
is
incorporated
into
one's endowment. Kahneman, Knetsch, and
Thaler
[1990] tested
the endowment effect
in
a
series
of
experiments,
conducted
in
a
classroom
setting.
In
one
of
these
experiments
a
decorated
mug
(retail value
of
about
$5) was
placed
in
front
of one third of
the
seats
after
students had chosen their
places.
All
participants
received a
questionnaire.
The
form
given
to
the recipients
of
a
mug
(the
"sellers")
indicated that "You now own
the
object
in
your
possession. You have the
option
of
selling
it
if
a
price,
which
will
be
determined
later,
is
acceptable
to
you.
For
each
of the
possible
prices
below
indicate whether
you
wish to
(x) Sell
your
object and
receive this
price;
(y) Keep your
object and take it home
with
you...."
The
subjects indicated their decision for
prices
ranging
from
$0.50
to
$9.50
in
steps
of
50
cents. Some of the
students who
had not
received a
mug (the
"choosers")
were given
a
similar
questionnaire,
informing
them
that
they
would have the
option
of
receiving
either
a
mug
or
a sum
of
money
to
be determined
later.
They indicated their
preferences between
a
mug
and
sums
of
money
ranging
from
$0.50
to
$9.50.
The
choosers and the
sellers
face
precisely the same
decision
problem,
but
their reference
states differ.
As
shown
in
Figure II,
the choosers'
reference state
is
t,
and
they
face
a
positive
choice
between two
options
that
dominate
t;
receiving
a
mug
or
receiving
a sum
in
cash. The
sellers evaluate the same
options
from
y; they
must choose
between
retaining
the
status
quo
(the mug)
or
giving
up
the
mug
in
exchange
for
money.
Thus,
the
mug
is evaluated as a
gain by
the
choosers,
and as
a loss
by
the
sellers. Loss
aversion
entails that
the rate
of
exchange
of
the
mug
against
money
will be
different
in
the
two
cases.
Indeed,
the median
value
of
the
mug
was
$7.12
for
the
sellers and
$3.12
for
the choosers
in
one
experiment,
$7.00
and
$3.50
in
another.
The difference
between these
values
reflects an
endowment effect
which
is
produced, apparently
instan-

1042
Q
UAR TERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
S0o
0
ci)
E t
----
x
cz~~~~~~~~~~~r
o~~~~~~~~s
Dimension
1
FIGURE II
Multiple Reference
Points for the Choice Between x and
y
taneously, by giving
an individual
property rights
over a
consump-
tion
good.
The interpretation of the endowment effect may be illumi-
nated by
the
following thought experiment.
Imagine
that as
a
chooser
you prefer $4
over
a
mug.
You learn
that
most
sellers
prefer
the
mug
to
$6,
and
you
believe that
if
you
had
the
mug you
would
do
the
same.
In
light
of this
knowledge,
would
you
now
prefer
the
mug
over
$5?
If
you do, it is presumably because you have changed your
assessment
of the
pleasure
associated with
owning
the
mug.
If
you
still
prefer $4
over the
mug-which
we
regard
as
a
more
likely
response this indicates that you interpret
the
effect
of endow-
ment as
an
aversion
to
giving up your mug
rather than as an
unanticipated
increase
in
the
pleasure
of
owning
it.
b. Status
Quo
Bias. The retention of the status
quo
is an
option
in
many
decision
problems.
As illustrated
by
the
analysis
of
the sellers'
problem
in
the
example
of the
mugs,
loss
aversion
induces a bias that favors
the
retention
of
the status
quo
over other
options.
In
Figure II,
a decision maker who is indifferent between x
and
y
from
t
will
prefer
x
over
y
from
x,
and
y
over x
from y.
Sarnuelson
and Zeckhauser
[1988]
introduced the term "status
quo
bias"
for
this effect
of
reference
position.

Citations
More filters
Journal Article•DOI•
TL;DR: Cumulative prospect theory as discussed by the authors applies to uncertain as well as to risky prospects with any number of outcomes, and it allows different weighting functions for gains and for losses, and two principles, diminishing sensitivity and loss aversion, are invoked to explain the characteristic curvature of the value function and the weighting function.
Abstract: We develop a new version of prospect theory that employs cumulative rather than separable decision weights and extends the theory in several respects. This version, called cumulative prospect theory, applies to uncertain as well as to risky prospects with any number of outcomes, and it allows different weighting functions for gains and for losses. Two principles, diminishing sensitivity and loss aversion, are invoked to explain the characteristic curvature of the value function and the weighting functions. A review of the experimental evidence and the results of a new experiment confirm a distinctive fourfold pattern of risk attitudes: risk aversion for gains and risk seeking for losses of high probability; risk seeking for gains and risk aversion for losses of low probability. Expected utility theory reigned for several decades as the dominant normative and descriptive model of decision making under uncertainty, but it has come under serious question in recent years. There is now general agreement that the theory does not provide an adequate description of individual choice: a substantial body of evidence shows that decision makers systematically violate its basic tenets. Many alternative models have been proposed in response to this empirical challenge (for reviews, see Camerer, 1989; Fishburn, 1988; Machina, 1987). Some time ago we presented a model of choice, called prospect theory, which explained the major violations of expected utility theory in choices between risky prospects with a small number of outcomes (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1986). The key elements of this theory are 1) a value function that is concave for gains, convex for losses, and steeper for losses than for gains,

13,433 citations

Journal Article•DOI•
TL;DR: This paper showed that if some people care about equity, the puzzles can be resolved and that the economic environment determines whether the fair types or the selesh types dominate equilibrium behavior in cooperative games.
Abstract: There is strong evidence that people exploit their bargaining power in competitivemarkets butnot inbilateral bargainingsituations. Thereisalsostrong evidence that people exploit free-riding opportunities in voluntary cooperation games. Yet, when they are given the opportunity to punish free riders, stable cooperation is maintained, although punishment is costly for those who punish. This paper asks whether there is a simple common principle that can explain this puzzling evidence. We show that if some people care about equity the puzzles can be resolved. It turns out that the economic environment determines whether the fair types or the selesh types dominate equilibrium behavior.

8,783 citations

Journal Article•DOI•
Ernst Fehr1•
TL;DR: This article showed that if a fraction of the people exhibit inequality aversion, stable cooperation is maintained although punishment is costly for those who punish, and they also showed that when they are given the opportunity to punish free riders, stable cooperations are maintained.
Abstract: There is strong evidence that people exploit their bargaining power in competitive markets but not in bilateral bargaining situations. There is also strong evidence that people exploit free-riding opportunities in voluntary cooperation games. Yet, when they are given the opportunity to punish free riders, stable cooperation is maintained although punishment is costly for those who punish. This paper asks whether there is a simple common principle that can explain this puzzling evidence. We show that if a fraction of the people exhibits inequality aversion the puzzles can be resolved.

6,919 citations


Cites background from "Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A..."

  • ...In 4 addition, Clark and Oswald [1996] show that comparison incomes have a significant impact on overall job satisfaction....

    [...]

Journal Article•DOI•
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors discuss the discounted utility (DU) model, its historical development, underlying assumptions, and "anomalies" -the empirical regularities that are inconsistent with its theoretical predictions.
Abstract: This paper discusses the discounted utility (DU) model: its historical development, underlying assumptions, and "anomalies" - the empirical regularities that are inconsistent with its theoretical predictions. We then summarize the alternate theoretical formulations that have been advanced to address these anomalies. We also review three decades of empirical research on intertemporal choice, and discuss reasons for the spectacular variation in implicit discount rates across studies. Throughout the paper, we stress the importance of distinguishing time preference, per se, from many other considerations that also influence intertemporal choices.

5,242 citations

Journal Article•DOI•
Daniel Kahneman1•
TL;DR: Determinants and consequences of accessibility help explain the central results of prospect theory, framing effects, the heuristic process of attribute substitution, and the characteristic biases that result from the substitution of nonextensional for extensional attributes.
Abstract: Early studies of intuitive judgment and decision making conducted with the late Amos Tversky are reviewed in the context of two related concepts: an analysis of accessibility, the ease with which thoughts come to mind; a distinction between effortless intuition and deliberate reasoning. Intuitive thoughts, like percepts, are highly accessible. Determinants and consequences of accessibility help explain the central results of prospect theory, framing effects, the heuristic process of attribute substitution, and the characteristic biases that result from the substitution of nonextensional for extensional attributes. Variations in the accessibility of rules explain the occasional corrections of intuitive judgments. The study of biases is compatible with a view of intuitive thinking and decision making as generally skilled and successful.

4,802 citations


Cites background from "Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A..."

  • ...The selling price often exceeds the buying price by a factor of 2 or more (Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1990, 1991; Tversky & Kahneman, 1991)....

    [...]

References
More filters
Book Chapter•DOI•
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors present a critique of expected utility theory as a descriptive model of decision making under risk, and develop an alternative model, called prospect theory, in which value is assigned to gains and losses rather than to final assets and in which probabilities are replaced by decision weights.
Abstract: This paper presents a critique of expected utility theory as a descriptive model of decision making under risk, and develops an alternative model, called prospect theory. Choices among risky prospects exhibit several pervasive effects that are inconsistent with the basic tenets of utility theory. In particular, people underweight outcomes that are merely probable in comparison with outcomes that are obtained with certainty. This tendency, called the certainty effect, contributes to risk aversion in choices involving sure gains and to risk seeking in choices involving sure losses. In addition, people generally discard components that are shared by all prospects under consideration. This tendency, called the isolation effect, leads to inconsistent preferences when the same choice is presented in different forms. An alternative theory of choice is developed, in which value is assigned to gains and losses rather than to final assets and in which probabilities are replaced by decision weights. The value function is normally concave for gains, commonly convex for losses, and is generally steeper for losses than for gains. Decision weights are generally lower than the corresponding probabilities, except in the range of low prob- abilities. Overweighting of low probabilities may contribute to the attractiveness of both insurance and gambling. EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY has dominated the analysis of decision making under risk. It has been generally accepted as a normative model of rational choice (24), and widely applied as a descriptive model of economic behavior, e.g. (15, 4). Thus, it is assumed that all reasonable people would wish to obey the axioms of the theory (47, 36), and that most people actually do, most of the time. The present paper describes several classes of choice problems in which preferences systematically violate the axioms of expected utility theory. In the light of these observations we argue that utility theory, as it is commonly interpreted and applied, is not an adequate descriptive model and we propose an alternative account of choice under risk. 2. CRITIQUE

35,067 citations

Journal Article•DOI•
TL;DR: Cumulative prospect theory as discussed by the authors applies to uncertain as well as to risky prospects with any number of outcomes, and it allows different weighting functions for gains and for losses, and two principles, diminishing sensitivity and loss aversion, are invoked to explain the characteristic curvature of the value function and the weighting function.
Abstract: We develop a new version of prospect theory that employs cumulative rather than separable decision weights and extends the theory in several respects. This version, called cumulative prospect theory, applies to uncertain as well as to risky prospects with any number of outcomes, and it allows different weighting functions for gains and for losses. Two principles, diminishing sensitivity and loss aversion, are invoked to explain the characteristic curvature of the value function and the weighting functions. A review of the experimental evidence and the results of a new experiment confirm a distinctive fourfold pattern of risk attitudes: risk aversion for gains and risk seeking for losses of high probability; risk seeking for gains and risk aversion for losses of low probability. Expected utility theory reigned for several decades as the dominant normative and descriptive model of decision making under uncertainty, but it has come under serious question in recent years. There is now general agreement that the theory does not provide an adequate description of individual choice: a substantial body of evidence shows that decision makers systematically violate its basic tenets. Many alternative models have been proposed in response to this empirical challenge (for reviews, see Camerer, 1989; Fishburn, 1988; Machina, 1987). Some time ago we presented a model of choice, called prospect theory, which explained the major violations of expected utility theory in choices between risky prospects with a small number of outcomes (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1986). The key elements of this theory are 1) a value function that is concave for gains, convex for losses, and steeper for losses than for gains,

13,433 citations

Journal Article•DOI•
Richard H. Thaler1•
TL;DR: The economic theory of the consumer is a combination of positive and normative theories as discussed by the authors, which describes how consumers should choose, but it is also described how they do choose, and in certain well-defined situations many consumers act in a manner that is inconsistent with economic theory.
Abstract: The economic theory of the consumer is a combination of positive and normative theories. Since it is based on a rational maximizing model it describes how consumers should choose, but it is alleged to also describe how they do choose. This paper argues that in certain well-defined situations many consumers act in a manner that is inconsistent with economic theory. In these situations economic theory will make systematic errors in predicting behavior. Kanneman and Tversey's prospect theory is proposed as the basis for an alternative descriptive theory. Topics discussed are: undeweighting of opportunity costs, failure to ignore sunk costs, scarch behavior choosing not to choose and regret, and precommitment and self-control.

5,099 citations

Journal Article•DOI•
TL;DR: A series of decision-making experiments showed that individuals disproportionately stick with the status quo as mentioned in this paper, that is, doing nothing or maintaining one's current or previous decision, and that this bias is substantial in important real decisions.
Abstract: Most real decisions, unlike those of economics texts, have a status quo alternative—that is, doing nothing or maintaining one's current or previous decision. A series of decision-making experiments shows that individuals disproportionately stick with the status quo. Data on the selections of health plans and retirement programs by faculty members reveal that the status quo bias is substantial in important real decisions. Economics, psychology, and decision theory provide possible explanations for this bias. Applications are discussed ranging from marketing techniques, to industrial organization, to the advance of science.

4,817 citations

Book Chapter•DOI•
01 Jan 1974
TL;DR: In this article, the authors discuss the association of income and happiness and suggest a Duesenberry-type model, involving relative status considerations as an important determinant of happiness.
Abstract: Publisher Summary This chapter discusses the association of income and happiness. The basic data consist of statements by individuals on their subjective happiness, as reported in thirty surveys from 1946 through 1970, covering nineteen countries, including eleven in Asia, Africa, and Latin America. Within countries, there is a noticeable positive association between income and happiness—in every single survey, those in the highest status group were happier, on the average, than those in the lowest status group. However, whether any such positive association exists among countries at a given time is uncertain. Certainly, the happiness differences between rich and poor countries that one might expect on the basis of the within-country differences by economic status are not borne out by the international data. Similarly, in the one national time series studied, for the United States since 1946, higher income was not systematically accompanied by greater happiness. As for why national comparisons among countries and over time show an association between income and happiness that is so much weaker than, if not inconsistent with, that shown by within-country comparisons, a Duesenberry-type model, involving relative status considerations as an important determinant of happiness, is suggested.

4,235 citations