scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal ArticleDOI

More evidence for sensorimotor adaptation in color perception.

01 Sep 2005-Journal of Vision (Association for Research in Vision and Ophthalmology)-Vol. 6, Iss: 2, pp 145-153
TL;DR: It is shown that sensorim motor adaptation can be obtained for color, as a consequence of the introduction of a new sensorimotor contingency between eye movements and color changes.
Abstract: Sensorimotor adaptation can be defined as a perceptual adaptation whose effects depend on the occurrence and nature of the performed motor actions. Examples of sensorimotor adaptation can be found in the literature on prisms concerning several space-related attributes like orientation, curvature, and size. In this article, we show that sensorimotor adaptation can be obtained for color, as a consequence of the introduction of a new sensorimotor contingency between eye movements and color changes. In an adaptation phase, trials involved the successive presentation of two patches, first on the left, and then on the right or the opposite. The left patch being always red and the right patch green, a correlation is introduced between left–right (respectively right–left) eye saccades and red–green (respectively green–red) color change. After 40 min of adaptation, when two yellow patches are successively presented on each side of the screen, the chromaticity of the left and right patches need respectively to be shifted toward the chromaticity of the red and green adaptation patches for subjective equality to be obtained. When the eyes are kept fixed during the adaptation stage, creating a strong nonhomogeneity in retinal adaptation, no effect is found. This ensures that, if present, adaptation at a given retinal location cannot explain the present effect. A third experiment shows a dependency of the effect on the eyes' saccadic movements and not on the position on the screen, that is, on the position of the eyes in the orbits. These results argue for the involvement of sensorimotor mechanisms in color perception. The relation of these experimental findings toward a sensorimotor theory of color perception is discussed.

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Citations
More filters
Journal Article
TL;DR: In this article, the authors propose that the brain produces an internal representation of the world, and the activation of this internal representation is assumed to give rise to the experience of seeing, but it leaves unexplained how the existence of such a detailed internal representation might produce visual consciousness.
Abstract: Many current neurophysiological, psychophysical, and psychological approaches to vision rest on the idea that when we see, the brain produces an internal representation of the world. The activation of this internal representation is assumed to give rise to the experience of seeing. The problem with this kind of approach is that it leaves unexplained how the existence of such a detailed internal representation might produce visual consciousness. An alternative proposal is made here. We propose that seeing is a way of acting. It is a particular way of exploring the environment. Activity in internal representations does not generate the experience of seeing. The outside world serves as its own, external, representation. The experience of seeing occurs when the organism masters what we call the governing laws of sensorimotor contingency. The advantage of this approach is that it provides a natural and principled way of accounting for visual consciousness, and for the differences in the perceived quality of sensory experience in the different sensory modalities. Several lines of empirical evidence are brought forward in support of the theory, in particular: evidence from experiments in sensorimotor adaptation, visual \"filling in,\" visual stability despite eye movements, change blindness, sensory substitution, and color perception.

2,271 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This review systematically investigated the role of temporal prediction, temporal control, identity prediction, and motor prediction in previous published reports of sensory attenuation and intentional binding, and assessed the degree to which existing data provide evidence for therole of forward action models in these phenomena.
Abstract: Sensory processing of action effects has been shown to differ from that of externally triggered stimuli, with respect both to the perceived timing of their occurrence (intentional binding) and to their intensity (sensory attenuation). These phenomena are normally attributed to forward action models, such that when action prediction is consistent with changes in our environment, our experience of these effects is altered. Although much progress has been made in recent years in understanding sensory attenuation and intentional binding, a number of important questions regarding the precise nature of the predictive mechanisms involved remain unanswered. Moreover, these mechanisms are often not discussed in empirical papers, and a comprehensive review of these issues is yet to appear. This review attempts to fill this void. We systematically investigated the role of temporal prediction, temporal control, identity prediction, and motor prediction in previous published reports of sensory attenuation and intentional binding. By isolating the individual processes that have previously been contrasted and incorporating these experiments with research in the related fields of temporal attention and stimulus expectation, we assessed the degree to which existing data provide evidence for the role of forward action models in these phenomena. We further propose a number of avenues for future research, which may help to better determine the role of motor prediction in processing of voluntary action effects, as well as to improve understanding of how these phenomena might fit within a general predictive processing framework. Furthermore, our analysis has important implications for understanding disorders of agency in schizophrenia.

331 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: By assuming that action preparation includes activation of the predicted sensory consequences of the action, this work provides a mechanism to understand sensory attenuation and intentional binding and proposes a possible neural basis for the processing of predicted action effects.

179 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The findings show that the human visual system can effectively use peripheral and foveal information about object features and that visual perception does not simply correspond to disconnected snapshots during each fixation.
Abstract: Due to the inhomogenous visual representation across the visual field, humans use peripheral vision to select objects of interest and foveate them by saccadic eye movements for further scrutiny. Thus, there is usually peripheral information available before and foveal information after a saccade. In this study we investigated the integration of information across saccades. We measured reliabilities--i.e., the inverse of variance-separately in a presaccadic peripheral and a postsaccadic foveal orientation--discrimination task. From this, we predicted trans-saccadic performance and compared it to observed values. We show that the integration of incongruent peripheral and foveal information is biased according to their relative reliabilities and that the reliability of the trans-saccadic information equals the sum of the peripheral and foveal reliabilities. Both results are consistent with and indistinguishable from statistically optimal integration according to the maximum-likelihood principle. Additionally, we tracked the gathering of information around the time of the saccade with high temporal precision by using a reverse correlation method. Information gathering starts to decline between 100 and 50 ms before saccade onset and recovers immediately after saccade offset. Altogether, these findings show that the human visual system can effectively use peripheral and foveal information about object features and that visual perception does not simply correspond to disconnected snapshots during each fixation.

103 citations


Cites background from "More evidence for sensorimotor adap..."

  • ...Several studies have shown that trans-saccadic changes in object features (Cox, Meier, Oertelt, & DiCarlo, 2005; Li & DiCarlo, 2008) and associations between saccade direction and postsaccadic foveal displays (Bompas & O’Regan, 2006) can be learned....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The results show that both selective attention and saccadic eye movements influenced the magnitude of the tilt aftereffect, but in different ways, suggesting that trans-saccadic perception is not limited to a single object but instead depends on the allocation of selective attention.

78 citations

References
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
R B Welch1

65 citations


"More evidence for sensorimotor adap..." refers background in this paper

  • ...Keywords: color, eye movements, sensorimotor, adaptation Introduction Adaptation to the spatial distortions introduced by prisms is a well-known phenomenon (Gibson, 1966; Harris, 1965; Held & Freedman, 1963; Rock, 1966; Welch, 1974)....

    [...]

  • ...Adaptation to the spatial distortions introduced by prisms is a well-known phenomenon (Gibson, 1966; Harris, 1965; Held & Freedman, 1963; Rock, 1966; Welch, 1974)....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Oct 2001-Synthese
TL;DR: The aims of this paper are to extend Susan Hurley's critique of the Duplication Assumption, to argue against highly constrained versions of Inverted Spectrum arguments, and to propose a broader conception of the vehicle for color perception.
Abstract: Susan Hurley has attacked the 'Duplication Assumption', the assumption thatcreatures with exactly the same internal states could function exactly alike inenvironments that are systematically distorted. She argues that the dynamicalinterdependence of action and perception is highly problematic for the DuplicationAssumption when it involves spatial states and capacities, whereas no such problemsarise when it involves color states and capacities. I will try to establish that theDuplication Assumption makes even less sense for lightness than for some ofthe spatial cases. This is due not only to motor factors, but to the basic physicalasymmetry between black and white. I then argue that the case can be extendedfrom lightness perception to hue perception. Overall, the aims of this paper are:(1) to extend Susan Hurley's critique of the Duplication Assumption; (2) to argueagainst highly constrained versions of Inverted Spectrum arguments; (3) to proposea broader conception of the vehicle for color perception.

51 citations


"More evidence for sensorimotor adap..." refers background in this paper

  • ...…actionVessentially eye movementsVin color perception have been discussed at several occasions in philosophical work (Broackes, 1992; Hurley, 1998; Myin, 2001) and artificial vision (Clark & O’Regan, 2000; Skaff, Arbel, & Clark 2002), in particular as a way to achieve color constancy using the…...

    [...]

  • ...However, the consequences of an involvement of actionVessentially eye movementsVin color perception have been discussed at several occasions in philosophical work (Broackes, 1992; Hurley, 1998; Myin, 2001) and artificial vision (Clark & O’Regan, 2000; Skaff, Arbel, & Clark 2002), in particular as a way to achieve color constancy using the nonuniformity of retinal sampling....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: Evidence that perception of colour is modified when an artificial coupling is introduced linking eye movements and colour changes is provided and argues for the involvement in colour perception of neural mechanisms continuously tuned to sensorimotor contingencies.
Abstract: Action is not usually considered to play a role in colour perception. However, sensorimotor theories of perception (eg O’Regan and Noe, 2001 Behavior and Brain Science 24 939 – 1011) suggest that, on the contrary, the transformations created by action in the sensory input are a necessary condition for all perception. In the case of colour vision, eye movements may explain how a retina with significant irregularities in resolution and cone arrangement (Roorda and Williams, 1999 Nature 397 520 – 522) could permit the perception of a richly coloured world (Clark and O’Regan, 2000 15th International Conference on Pattern Recognition volume 2: Pattern Recognition and Neural Networks pp 503 – 506; Skaff et al, 2002 16th International Conference on Pattern Recognition volume 2, pp 681 – 684). We provide evidence that perception of colour is modified when an artificial coupling is introduced linking eye movements and colour changes. After 40 min of wearing left-field-blue/right-field-yellow spectacles, observers’ colour vision adapts so that, after removing the spectacles, white patches seem to become bluer when the eyes move rightwards and yellower when the eyes move leftwards. This induced dependence of colour perception on the direction of eye saccade is shown to be related to the amount of eye movements during exposure. This result, which cannot be explained either by retinal adaptation, or by a conditioned association between colour and side, constitutes first clear evidence for a role of eye movements in perceived colour and argues for the involvement in colour perception of neural mechanisms continuously tuned to sensorimotor contingencies.

50 citations


"More evidence for sensorimotor adap..." refers background or result in this paper

  • ...The results observed in the present study confirmed the conclusion of our previous spectacle experiment (Bompas & O’Regan, 2006): The method we used produced a perceptual change that can neither be interpreted as a purely physiological adaptation of cone sensitivity nor as a conditioning between…...

    [...]

  • ...In a recent series of experiments, Bompas and O’Regan (2006) also had subjects wear left-field yellow/rightfield blue spectacles but for a different purpose....

    [...]

  • ...In Bompas and O’Regan (2006), as in Kohler’s (1962), a large part of the visual field was tinted yellow when the subject gazed leftward and tinted blue when the gaze was directed rightward....

    [...]

  • ...Contrary to the first-mentioned contingency, absolute and static, this second one, relative and dynamic, proved to be easily subject to adaptation (Bompas & O’Regan, 2006)....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI

39 citations


"More evidence for sensorimotor adap..." refers background or result in this paper

  • ...Half-split colored spectacles introduce a correlation between gaze direction and color, but as McCullough (1965) showed, no contingent adaptation linking these two kinds of sensory inputs can be obtained....

    [...]

  • ...However, his results failed to be replicated by better-controlled attempts (McCullough, 1965), even with longer exposure (Harrington, 1965)....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: A very small change in perceived color could be noticed as the gaze was moved back and forth from right to left without the glasses on, but this may have an explanation at the ocular level.
Abstract: “Split-field” glasses, consisting of a red filter before the left half-field of each eye and a green filter before the right half-field, were worn by three observers. The colors in the glasses did not seem to diminish in saturation as Kohler (1951) has reported, even after as long as 146 days. A very small change in perceived color could be noticed as the gaze was moved back and forth from right to left without the glasses on, but this may have an explanation at the ocular level.

14 citations


"More evidence for sensorimotor adap..." refers result in this paper

  • ...However, his results failed to be replicated by better-controlled attempts (McCullough, 1965), even with longer exposure (Harrington, 1965)....

    [...]