scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal ArticleDOI

Optimal risk sharing for law invariant monetary utility functions

01 Apr 2008-Mathematical Finance (Blackwell Publishing Inc)-Vol. 18, Iss: 2, pp 269-292
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors consider the problem of optimal risk sharing of some given total risk between two economic agents characterized by law-invariant monetary utility functions or equivalently, law invariant risk measures.
Abstract: We consider the problem of optimal risk sharing of some given total risk between two economic agents characterized by law-invariant monetary utility functions or equivalently, law-invariant risk measures. We first prove existence of an optimal risk sharing allocation which is in addition increasing in terms of the total risk. We next provide an explicit characterization in the case where both agents’ utility functions are comonotone. The general form of the optimal contracts turns out to be given by a sum of options (stop-loss contracts, in the language of insurance) on the total risk. In order to show the robustness of this type of contracts to more general utility functions, we introduce a new notion of strict risk aversion conditionally on lower tail events, which is typically satisfied by the semi-deviation and the entropic risk measures. Then, in the context of an AV@R-agent facing an agent with strict monotone preferences and exhibiting strict risk aversion conditional on lower tail events, we prove that optimal contracts again are European options on the total risk. MSC 1991 subject classifications: Primary 91B06, 46A20; secondary 91B70.

Summary (3 min read)

1 Introduction

  • The purpose of this paper is to obtain an explicit characterization of the optimal risk sharing in the context of monetary utility functions, see Definition 2.1 below.
  • The class of monetary utility functions which satisfy these two conditions include the so-called entropic utility and the semi-deviation utility (see e.g. [23]).
  • In particular this shows that Agent 0 takes the extremal risks, and that the AV@R measure of risk is not so prudent.
  • The authors believe that the above stated results provide an additional justification for the existence of options in financial markets, and stop-loss contracts, deductibles and layers in insurance markets.

2.1 Monetary utility functions

  • Observe that the cash invariance and the monotonicity of U imply that U is finite and Lipschitz-continuous on L∞. Monetary utility functions can be identified with convex risk measures by the formula ρ(ξ) = −U(ξ).
  • Assuming the Fatou property, suppose that a monetary utility function U is positively homogeneous, i.e. U(ξ) = −ρ(ξ) for some coherent risk measure ρ.
  • For later use, the authors provide the following well-known properties and their proof for completeness, see e.g. [6].

2.2 Law-invariance

  • L∞ for any pair (U0, U1) of law-invariant monetary utility functions.
  • Given two law-invariant monetary utility functions U0 and U1, the authors know from Lemma 2.1 and (2.2) that U0 U1 is a monetary utility function.
  • An interesting characterization of law-invariant monetary utility functions, obtained by Kusuoka [32] and further extended in [22] and [29].
  • (Theorem 2.1 and equation (14)), expresses any law-invariant coherent risk measure in terms of the quantile function.
  • C↘ is not continuous at this point (see Remark 2.4 below).

3.1 Pareto optimal allocations

  • The authors first recall some classical notions from economic theory, see e.g. Gerber [26].
  • X} is called the set of attainable allocations.
  • Theorem 3.1. Let U0 and U1 be two monetary utility functions with associated convex conjugate functions V0 and V1 defined on (L∞)∗.
  • Equivalence with (vi) in the law-invariant context is new.

3.2 The existence result

  • X} be the subset of admissible allocations which increase with the corresponding aggregate risk.
  • By the Denneberg’s lemma [16], the authors observe that A↗(X) is the subset of A(X) consisting of all comonotone allocations.
  • The following result is proved in Section 6, where the authors also discuss the fact that the law-invariance assumption can not be dropped.
  • Theorem 3.2. Let U0 and U1 be two law-invariant monetary utility functions.

3.3 Two concrete examples

  • After having established the existence of Pareto optimal allocations, the authors now give an explicit characterization of Pareto optimal allocations in A↗(X) for some specific lawinvariant monetary utility functions.
  • The authors first consider the case where both agents are defined by comonotone law-invariant monetary utility functions.
  • The following easy application relates this result to options or stop-loss contracts, layers and deductibles in insurance.
  • L∞+ \{0}, with a strict risk-aversion property to be defined below.
  • Before turning to the precise definition of the latter restriction, the authors state their second main concrete example.

3.4 The semi-deviation utility

  • This can be easily checked in the following example.
  • For p = 1, the semi-deviation utility is not strictly risk averse conditionally on lower tail events.

3.6 Optimal risk sharing allocations

  • The explicit Pareto optimal allocations obtained in Propositions 3.1 and 3.2 induce optimal risk sharing rules.
  • Obviously, under the condition (IR) of individual rationality, the agents can agree to exchange the risk ξ if and only if p0(ξ) ≤ p1(ξ).
  • In view of the discussion preceding the theorem, the authors only need to show that p0(ξ∗) ≤ p1(ξ∗).
  • Of course, the value of ε depends strongly on the design of these experiments, and the real-life situation to which the present model is applied.

4 Super-gradient of law-invariant monetary utility functions

  • The main purpose of this section is to prove Proposition 3.1.
  • The authors start by considering law-invariant monetary utility functions, before specializing the discussion to the comonotone case.
  • This contradiction shows that (i) holds true.
  • The authors next specialize the discussion to the comonotone case.

5 Strict risk aversion conditionally on lower-tail events

  • The crucial arguments are isolated in the two following lemmas.
  • Let U be a law-invariant monetary utility function which is strictly risk averse conditionally on lower tail events.
  • The authors are now ready for the Proof of Proposition 3.2 Let (ξ0, ξ1) ∈ A↗(X) be a Pareto optimal allocation.

6.1 A duality argument

  • This provides a partial proof of Theorem 3.2 which states in addition that a Pareto optimal allocation exists in the smaller set A↗(X).
  • L∞ for law-invariant monetary utility functions U0 and U1.
  • As a by-product, the authors obtain Lemma 6.2 which states that the existence statement is actually equivalent to the identity (6.2) which, in particular, yields a proof for (6.2).
  • Notice that that the law-invariance assumption cannot be dropped, as shown in Subsection 6.3 below.

6.2 A direct existence argument

  • Lemma 6.1. Let U0 and U1 be two law-invariant monetary utility functions.
  • The authors first recall that any attainable allocation (ξ0, ξ1) ∈ A(X) is dominated by some comonotone attainable allocation (ξ̂0, ξ̂1) ∈ A(X) in the sense of second order stochastic dominance.
  • This result was proved by Landsberger and Meilijson [33] in the context of a finite probability space, and further extended to L∞ allocations in a general probability space by Dana and Meilijson [14].
  • By Corollary 4.59 in [25], any law-invariant monetary utility function preserves second order stochastic dominance, which provides Ui ( ξ̂i ) ≥ Ui (ξi) .
  • This justifies the duality-based existence argument reported in the beginning of Section 6. Lemma 6.2. Proof. (ii)=⇒(i) : Under (ii), the argument in the beginning of this section provides the required existence result.

Did you find this useful? Give us your feedback

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Optimal risk sharing for law invariant monetary utility
functions
E. Jouini
W. Schachermayer
N. Touzi
April 19, 2007
Abstract
We consider the problem of optimal risk sharing of some given total risk be-
tween two economic agents characterized by law-invariant monetary utility functions
or equivalently, law-invariant risk measures. We first prove existence of an optimal risk
sharing allocation which is in addition increasing in terms of the total risk. We next
provide an explicit characterization in the case where both agents’ utility functions are
comonotone. The general form of the optimal contracts turns out to be given by a sum
of options (stop-loss contracts, in the language of insurance) on the total risk. In order
to show the robustness of this type of contracts to more general utility functions, we
introduce a new notion of strict risk aversion conditionally on lower tail events, which
is typically satisfied by the semi-deviation and the entropic risk measures. Then, in
the context of an AV@R-agent facing an agent with strict monotone preferences and
exhibiting strict risk aversion conditional on lower tail events, we prove that optimal
contracts again are European options on the total risk.
MSC 1991 subject classifications: Primary 91B06, 46A20; secondary 91B70.
Key words : Monetary utility functions, comonotonicity, Pareto optimal allocations.
Universit´e Paris Dauphine and CEREMADE, Place du Mar´echal de Lattre de Tassigny, F-75775 Paris
Cedex 16, France.
Vienna University of Technology, Wiedner Hauptstrasse 8-10/105, A-1040 Wien, Austria and Univer-
sit´e Paris Dauphine, Place du Mar´echal de Lattre de Tassigny, F-75775 Paris Cedex 16, France. Financial
support from the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) under the grant P15889 and from Vienna Science and
Technology Fund (WWTF) under Grant MA13 is gratefully acknowledged.
CREST, Laboratoire de Finance et Assurance, 15 Bd Gabriel P´e ri, F-92245 Malakoff Cedex, France
and Universit´e Paris Dauphine, Place du Mar´echal de L attre de Tassigny, F-75775 Paris Cedex 16, France.
1

1 Introduction
The problem of optimal sharing of risk between two agents has been considered by many
authors, starting from Arrow [1], Borch [9], B¨uhlmann [7], B¨uhlmann and Jewell [8], see
also Gerber [26]. The main motivation was the application to insurance problems. For an
extensive list of references, we refer to the recent paper by Dana and Scarsini [15] and the
second edition of the b ook by ollmer and Schied [25]. The general setting of the problem
is the following. The initial risk endowments of the agents are defined by the bounded
random variables X
0
and X
1
, so that the aggregate risk is given by X := X
0
+ X
1
. An
allocation (ξ
0
, ξ
1
), with ξ
0
+ξ
1
= X, is c alled an optimal risk sharing if it is Pareto optimal
and satisfies the individual rationality constraint, i.e. none of the agents exp e riences a loss
of utility by passing from X
i
to ξ
i
.
The purpose of this paper is to obtain an explicit characterization of the optimal risk
sharing in the context of monetary utility functions, see Definition 2.1 below. Up to the
sign, monetary utility functions are identical to convex risk measures [24, 21], a popular
notion in particular since the Basel II acc ord. Indeed, U is a monetary utility function
if and only if ρ = U is a convex risk measure in the sense of ollmer and Schied [24],
Frittelli and Rosazza-Gianin [21]. We shall rather use the language of monetary utility
functions in order to embed our analysis in the setting of classical utility theory. Our
framework is mainly motivated by Barrieu and El Karoui [3, 4, 5, 6] who showed that,
when the agents’ utilities are given by U
i
(ξ) := γ
1
i
U(γ
i
ξ) for some γ
i
> 0 and some
monetary utility function U, the optimal risk sharing rule is proportional to the aggregate
risk. We also refer to Heath and Ku [27] for analyzing Pareto optimal risk between banks
defined by coherent risk measures in a finite probability space.
In comparison to the ge neral utility theory, the setting of monetary utility functions
induces a remarkable simplification, as it induces a clear separation between the Pareto
optimality and the individual rationality constraints which define an optimal risk sharing
rule. Pareto optimal allocations are defined up to a constant, and their characterization
reduces to the calculation of the sup-convolution of the utility functions, as observed in
[3]. As a second independent step, the choice of the constant, or the premium, inside
the interval of reservation prices of the agents then characterizes all optimal risk s haring
allocations.
In this paper, we specialize further the class of monetary utility functions by assuming
the law-invariance property. Under this condition, we prove that the set of optimal risk
sharing allocations is not empty. We next derive an explicit characterization of optimal
risk sharing allocations in two concrete settings :
(i) When the preferences of both agents are defined by comonotone law-invariant utility
functions (a typical example being U = AV @R
α
to be discussed below), a precise de-
2

scription of the optimal risk sharing rule is provided. The key-ingredient is the quantile
representation of Kusuoka [32] which is further extended in [22], [25] and [29]. We prove
that Pareto optimal allocations are given by sums of European options (“stop-loss con-
tracts” or simply “deductibles” in the insurance terminology) written on the aggregate
risk X. We observe that this setting is intimately connected to the context of convex
distorsions of probability as studied in Carlier and Dana [12].
(ii) As a s ec ond example, we fix some α (0, 1), and we assume that the utility of Agent
0 is defined by U
0
= AV @R
α
, where AV @R
α
is the so-called average value at risk or
expected shortfall risk measure. This is the prime example of a comonotone monetary
utility function. Agent 1 is defined by a law-invariant monetary utility function which is
strictly monotone. We further assume that Agent 1 is strictly risk averse conditionally on
lower tail events. This notion is defined in Section 3. Loosely s peaking, it states that the
agent has a strict preference for averaging lower tail events of risk. The class of monetary
utility functions which satisfy these two conditions include the so-called entropic utility
and the semi-deviation utility (see e.g. [23]). We remark that U
0
= AV @R
α
is neither
strictly monotone, nor strictly risk averse conditionally on lower tail events. In the above
setting, we show that Pareto optimal allocations are defined by class ical options : Agent 0
offers a stop-loss contract defined by a threshold κ, and leaves Agent 1 with the aggregate
risk capped at the level κ, i.e. (ξ
0
, ξ
1
) = ((X κ)
, κ X). In particular this shows that
Agent 0 takes the extremal risks, and that the AV@R measure of risk is not so prudent.
We believe that the above stated results provide an additional justification for the ex-
istence of options in financial markets, and stop-loss contracts, deductibles and layers in
insurance markets.
We c onclude this introduction by pointing out the importance of the concavity of the
utility function. It was stressed in [2] that the V@R criterion for risk measuring leads
to incoherent results because of the lack of sub-additivity. The present context of risk
sharing provides another result in this direction. Indeed, let Agent 1 be defined by
any monetary utility function. Assuming that Agent 0 is defined by the utility function
U
0
= V @R
α
(X), it follows clearly that the level of the random variable on the event set
{X < V@R
α
(X)} is not relevant for this agent. Then, an optimal risk sharing allocation
consists in endorsing her any large amount of risk on the event set {X < V@R
α
(X)} ! In
other words, the V @R
α
agent endorses an infinite amount of risk with positive proba-
bility. Hence the very question of optimal risk sharing leads to silly results if one of the
agents uses the V@R criterion as a measure of risk.
The paper is organized as follows. Sec tion 2 collects some notions on monetary utility
functions. Our main results are state d in Section 3. Section 4 is devoted to the charac-
terization of the optimal sharing allocations when both agents are defined by comonotone
law-invariant monetary utility functions. In Section 5, we focus on the notion of strict
3

risk aversion, conditional on lower tail events, together with its implications in terms of
risk sharing. Finally, we report the existence of optimal risk sharing allocations under
law-invariant monetary utility functions in Section 6.
2 Preliminaries : utility functions and related notions
Throughout this paper, we work on a standard probability space (Ω, F, P), i.e. we suppose
that (Ω, F, P) has no atoms and that L
2
(Ω, F, P) is separable. For every p [0, ], we
shall denote by L
p
(P) the collection of all real-valued random variables with finite L
p
norm
under P. Here, L
0
:= L
0
(P) c onsists of all real-valued Fmeasurable random variables,
and L
:= L
(P) is the subset of all essentially bounded elements in L
0
.
For every random variable ξ with values in R, we denote its cumulative distribution
function by F
ξ
(x) := P[ξ x], and its generalized inverse (called quantile function) by
q
ξ
(α) = inf {x : F
ξ
(x) α} for α [0, 1].
Given two random variables ξ and ζ, we shall write ξ =
d
ζ to indicate equality in
distribution.
For a bounded finitely additive measure µ (L
)
, we denote by kµk
ba
its total mass.
Given a sub-σ-algebra G of F, we define the conditional expectation (L
)
3 µ 7−
E[µ|G] (L
)
as the transpose of the Gconditional expectation operator on L
, i.e.
hE[µ|G], ξi = hµ, E[ξ|G]i for all µ (L
)
and ξ L
. If the singular part of µ is zero,
i.e. µ is absolutely continuous with respect to P with density dµ/dP = Z, then it is
immediately checked that this definition coincides with the classical notion of condition
expectation in the sense that E[µ|G] = E[Z|G] · P.
Let E be a Banach space with dual E
. Given a function f : E R, its sub-gradient
and super-gradients are respectively denoted by
f(x) := {x
E
: f(y) f(x) + hx
, y xi for every y E} ,
+
f(x) := {x
E
: f(y) f(x) + hx
, y xi for every y E} .
When f is convex (resp. concave), we shall simply denote f :=
f (resp. f :=
+
f).
2.1 Monetary utility functions
We say that a function f : L
[−∞, ] is proper if dom(U ) := {ξ L
: U(ξ) R}
is non-empty.
Definition 2.1. A proper function U : L
R is called a mon etary utility function if it
is concave, monotone with respect to the order of L
, satisfies the normalization condition
4

U(0) = 0 and has the cash-invariance property
U(ξ + c) = U(ξ) + c for every ξ L
and c R .
Observe that the cash invariance and the monotonicity of U imply that U is finite and
Lipschitz-continuous on L
. In particular, the normalization U(0) = 0 does not restrict
the generality as it may be obtained by adding a constant to U.
Monetary utility functions can be identified with convex risk measures by the formula
ρ(ξ) = U(ξ). In particular, positively homogeneous monetary utility functions can be
identified with coherent risk measures, introduced in Artzner, Delbaen, Eber and Heath [2],
while the general notion of monetary utility functions corresponds to convex risk measures
as introduced independently by ollmer and Schied [24], and Frittelli and Rossaza-Gianin
[21]. We shall frequently use the conjugate function
V (µ) := sup
ξL
(U(ξ) hµ, ξi) R {∞} , µ (L
)
,
which is convex and lower semi-continuous with respect to σ ((L
)
, L
). From classical
convex duality theory, see e.g. [10], and the L
continuity of U, it follows that U and V
are hL
, (L
)
i−conjugate, i.e.
U(ξ) = inf
µ(L
)
(V (µ) + hµ, ξi) for every ξ L
.
We shall denote by V
1
the restriction of V to L
1
(P), and remark that its domain is included
in the set of densities of P-absolutely continuous probability measures, i.e.
dom(V
1
) :=
Z L
1
(P) : V (Z) <
Z :=
Z L
1
+
(P) : E[Z] = 1
.(2.1)
Theorem 2.1 ([19, 24]). For a monetary utility function U , the following statements are
equivalent :
(i) U and V
1
are hL
, L
1
(P)i−conjugate, i.e. U(ξ) = inf
ZL
1
(P)
V
1
(Z) + E[Zξ]
for
ξ L
,
(ii) U is σ
L
, L
1
(P)
upper semicontinuous,
(iii) U has the Fatou property, i.e. for every L
bounded sequence (ξ
n
)
n1
converging in
probability to some ξ L
, we have U(ξ) lim sup
n
U(ξ
n
).
Remark 2.1. Assuming the Fatou property, suppose that a monetary utility function U
is positively homogeneous, i.e. U(ξ) = ρ(ξ) for some coherent risk measure ρ. Then, the
conjugate function V is zero on its domain, and U (X) = inf
Zdom(V
1
)
E[ZX].
Given two monetary utility functions U
0
and U
1
, we denote by
U
0
U
1
(ξ) := sup
ξ
0
L
U
0
(ξ
0
) + U
1
(ξ ξ
0
) , ξ L
,
5

Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, a dual characterization of law invariant coherent risk measures, satisfying the Fatou property, was given, and the notion of the Lebesgue property of a convex risk measure was introduced.
Abstract: S. Kusuoka [K 01, Theorem 4] gave an interesting dual characterization of law invariant coherent risk measures, satisfying the Fatou property. The latter property was introduced by F. Delbaen [D 02]. In the present note we extend Kusuoka's characterization in two directions, the first one being rather standard, while the second one is somewhat surprising. Firstly we generalize — similarly as M. Fritelli and E. Rossaza Gianin [FG05] — from the notion of coherent risk measures to the more general notion of convex risk measures as introduced by H. F¨ollmer and A. Schied [FS 04]. Secondly — and more importantly — we show that the hypothesis of Fatou property may actually be dropped as it is automatically implied by the hypothesis of law invariance.We also introduce the notion of the Lebesgue property of a convex risk measure, where the inequality in the definition of the Fatou property is replaced by an equality, and give some dual characterizations of this property.

252 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors study the convolution of abstract conditional convex risk measures and show that they preserve the dynamic property of time-consistency, and construct a dynamic risk measure (or utility functional) associated to superreplication in a market with trading constraints.
Abstract: The (subjective) indifference value of a payoff in an incomplete financial market is that monetary amount which leaves an agent indifferent between buying or not buying the payoff when she always optimally exploits her trading opportunities. We study these values over time when they are defined with respect to a dynamic monetary concave utility functional, that is, minus a dynamic convex risk measure. For that purpose, we prove some new results about families of conditional convex risk measures. We study the convolution of abstract conditional convex risk measures and show that it preserves the dynamic property of time-consistency. Moreover, we construct a dynamic risk measure (or utility functional) associated to superreplication in a market with trading constraints and prove that it is time-consistent. By combining these results, we deduce that the corresponding indifference valuation functional is again time-consistent. As an auxiliary tool, we establish a variant of the representation theorem for conditional convex risk measures in terms of equivalent probability measures.

205 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the problem of finding a market portfolio that minimizes the convex risk measure of the terminal wealth in a jump diffusion market is formulated as a two-player stochastic differential game.
Abstract: In this paper, we consider the problem to find a market portfolio that minimizes the convex risk measure of the terminal wealth in a jump diffusion market. We formulate the problem as a two player (zero-sum) stochastic differential game. To help us find a solution, we prove a theorem giving the Hamilton–Jacobi–Bellman–Isaacs (HJBI) conditions for a general zero-sum stochastic differential game in a jump diffusion setting. We then use the theorem to study particular risk minimization problems. Finally, we extend our approach to cover general stochastic differential games (not necessarily zero-sum), and we obtain similar HJBI equations for the Nash equilibria of such games.

150 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, a new class of risk measures called cash sub-additive risk measures is introduced to assess the risk of future financial, non-financial and insurance positions, which can model stochastic and/or ambiguous interest rates or defaultable contingent claims.
Abstract: A new class of risk measures called cash sub-additive risk measures is introduced to assess the risk of future financial, non financial and insurance positions. The debated cash additive axiom is relaxed into the cash sub-additive axiom to preserve the original difference between the numeraire of the current reserve amounts and future positions. Consequently, cash sub-additive risk measures can model stochastic and/or ambiguous interest rates or defaultable contingent claims. Practical examples are presented and in such contexts cash additive risk measures cannot be used. Several representations of the cash sub-additive risk measures are provided. The new risk measures are characterized by penalty functions defined on a set of sub-linear probability measures and can be represented using penalty functions associated with cash additive risk measures defined on some extended spaces. The issue of the optimal risk transfer is studied in the new framework using inf-convolution techniques.Examples of dynamic cash sub-additive risk measures are provided via BSDEs where the generator can locally depend on the level of the cash sub-additive risk measure.

144 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, a dual characterization of quasiconvex cash-subadditive risk measures is provided and necessary and sufficient conditions for their law invariance are established, as well as an alternative characterization of the actuarial mean value premium principle.
Abstract: When there is uncertainty about interest rates (typically due to either illiquidity or defaultability of zero coupon bonds) the cash-additivity assumption on risk measures becomes problematic. When this assumption is weakened, to cash-subadditivity for example, the equivalence between convexity and the diversification principle no longer holds. In fact, this principle only implies (and it is implied by) quasiconvexity. For this reason, in this paper quasiconvex risk measures are studied. We provide a dual characterization of quasiconvex cash-subadditive risk measures and we establish necessary and sufficient conditions for their law invariance. As a byproduct, we obtain an alternative characterization of the actuarial mean value premium principle.

132 citations


Cites background from "Optimal risk sharing for law invari..."

  • ...DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9965.2010.00450.x C© 2010 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. 743 Frittelli and Rosazza Gianin (2004), Staum (2004), Filipović and Kupper (2008), and Jouini, Schachermayer, and Touzi (2008)....

    [...]

References
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors present and justify a set of four desirable properties for measures of risk, and call the measures satisfying these properties "coherent", and demonstrate the universality of scenario-based methods for providing coherent measures.
Abstract: In this paper we study both market risks and nonmarket risks, without complete markets assumption, and discuss methods of measurement of these risks. We present and justify a set of four desirable properties for measures of risk, and call the measures satisfying these properties “coherent.” We examine the measures of risk provided and the related actions required by SPAN, by the SEC=NASD rules, and by quantile-based methods. We demonstrate the universality of scenario-based methods for providing coherent measures. We offer suggestions concerning the SEC method. We also suggest a method to repair the failure of subadditivity of quantile-based methods.

8,651 citations


"Optimal risk sharing for law invari..." refers background in this paper

  • ...It was stressed in [2] that the V@R criterion for risk measuring leads to incoherent results because of the lack of sub-additivity....

    [...]

  • ...It was stressed in Artzner et al. (1999) that the V@R criterion for risk measuring leads to incoherent results because of the lack of sub-additivity....

    [...]

  • ...We also refer to Heath and Ku (2004) for analyzing Pareto optimal risk between banks defined by coherent risk measures in a finite probability space....

    [...]

  • ...In particular, positively homogeneous monetary utility functions can be identified with coherent risk measures, introduced in Artzner, Delbaen, Eber and Heath [2], while the general notion of monetary utility functions corresponds to convex risk measures as introduced independently by Föllmer and Schied [24], and Frittelli and Rossaza-Gianin [21]....

    [...]

  • ...In particular, positively homogeneous monetary utility functions can be identified with coherent risk measures, introduced in Artzner et al. (1999), while the general notion of monetary utility functions corresponds to convex risk measures as introduced independently by Föllmer and Schied (2002)…...

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This article found that the canonical model is not supported in any society studied, and that group-level differences in economic organization and the degree of market integration explain a substantial portion of the behavioral variation across societies.
Abstract: We can summarize our results as follows. First, the canonical model is not supported in any society studied. Second, there is considerably more behavioral variability across groups than had been found in previous cross-cultural research, and the canonical model fails in a wider variety of ways than in previous experiments. Third, group-level differences in economic organization and the degree of market integration explain a substantial portion of the behavioral variation across societies: the higher the degree of market integration and the higher the payoffs to cooperation, the greater the level of cooperation in experimental games. Fourth, individual-level economic and demographic variables do not explain behavior either within or across groups. Fifth, behavior in the experiments is generally consistent with economic patterns of everyday life in these societies.

2,019 citations

Book Chapter
01 Jan 1990
TL;DR: A behavioral game theory that explains the initial deviations (and their disappearance) could be useful, especially if the learning process is modeled carefully and better data are gathered as mentioned in this paper. But, with experience, these deviations sometimes disappear.
Abstract: People deviate from the predictions of game theory in two systematic ways. They are not purely self-interested (they care about fairness and try to cooperate with others), and they do not always consider what other players will do before making choices. However, with experience, these deviations sometimes disappear. People learn when they can afford to be unfair and what others will do; their behavior often converges to a game-theoretic equilibrium. A behavioral game theory that explains the initial deviations (and their disappearance) could be useful, especially if the learning process is modeled carefully and better data are gathered.

1,596 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors introduce the notion of a convex measure of risk, an extension of the concept of a coherent risk measure defined in Artzner et al. (1999), and prove a corresponding extension of representation theorem in terms of probability measures on the underlying space of scenarios.
Abstract: We introduce the notion of a convex measure of risk, an extension of the concept of a coherent risk measure defined in Artzner et al. (1999), and we prove a corresponding extension of the representation theorem in terms of probability measures on the underlying space of scenarios. As a case study, we consider convex measures of risk defined in terms of a robust notion of bounded shortfall risk. In the context of a financial market model, it turns out that the representation theorem is closely related to the superhedging duality under convex constraints.

1,302 citations

Frequently Asked Questions (11)
Q1. What have the authors contributed in "Optimal risk sharing for law invariant monetary utility functions" ?

The authors consider the problem of optimal risk sharing of some given total risk between two economic agents characterized by law-invariant monetary utility functions or equivalently, law-invariant risk measures. The authors first prove existence of an optimal risk sharing allocation which is in addition increasing in terms of the total risk. The authors next provide an explicit characterization in the case where both agents ’ utility functions are comonotone. In order to show the robustness of this type of contracts to more general utility functions, the authors introduce a new notion of strict risk aversion conditionally on lower tail events, which is typically satisfied by the semi-deviation and the entropic risk measures. Then, in the context of an AV @ R-agent facing an agent with strict monotone preferences and exhibiting strict risk aversion conditional on lower tail events, the authors prove that optimal contracts again are European options on the total risk. 

A measure preserving transformation of (Ω,F ,P) is a bi-measurable bijection τ : (Ω,F ,P) → (Ω,F ,P) leaving P invariant, i.e., τ(P) = P. 

Pareto optimal allocations are only defined up to a constant, i.e. given a Pareto optimal allocation (ξ0, ξ1), the attainable allocation (ξ0 + c, ξ1− c) is also Pareto optimal for every c ∈ R, 2. Let (ξ0, ξ1) be an attainable allocation which is not Pareto optimal. 

Let U0 and U1 be two comonotone law-invariant monetary utility functions, and let ϕ̄0, ϕ̄1 ∈ C↘ be the associated functions in the representation (2.3). 

By Lemma 4.2, the authors see thatqξ0 is constant on [β, 1] . (5.4)Since U1 is strictly risk-averse conditionally on lower tail events, it follows again from the comonotonicity of the pairs (−Z, ξi), i = 0, 1, together with Lemma 5.1 thatqξ1 is constant on [0, β] . 

By Remark 2.3, the functions Ui and V 1i = χCϕ̄i are 〈L ∞,L1(P)〉−conjugate, where χ is the indicator function in the sense of convex analysis. 

2The characterization (ii) in the above Theorem 3.1 has a well-known extension for general utility functions (see e.g. [26]), which involves two Lagrange multipliers (simply leaving out the last sentence in the above proof of (i)=⇒(ii)). 

In this example due to F. Delbaen [20], the authors show that the set of Pareto optimal allocations might be empty in the context where all monetary utility functions U0, U1, U0 U1, are positively-homogeneous, and have the Fatou property. 

The authors first start by proving that the maximization problem in the definition of the supconvolution U0 U1 can be restricted to pairs (ξ0, ξ1) ∈ A↗(X). 

D↘ } and its pointwise closureC↘ = {ϕ : [0, 1] −→ [0, 1] non-decreasing, concave, ϕ(0) = 0 and ϕ(1) = 1} .Clearly, C↘ is the subset of all functions in C↘ which are continuous at the point t = 0. 

This example was triggered by a question of N. El Karoui, and shows that, even in a finite-dimensional setting, it may happen that the set of Pareto optimal allocations is empty for any possible aggregate risk X ∈ L∞.