scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal ArticleDOI

Reflexivity and its Consequences

01 Aug 1999-European Journal of Social Theory (SAGE Publications)-Vol. 2, Iss: 3, pp 298-306
TL;DR: The work of Pierre Bourdieu owes much of its distinctive qualities to its reflexive character, to the incisive and recurrent analysis of what it means to practise social science, to be an academic, or to speak out as an intellectual as mentioned in this paper.
Abstract: The work of Pierre Bourdieu owes much of its distinctive qualities to its reflexive character, to the incisive and recurrent analysis of what it means to practise social science, to be an academic, or to speak out as an intellectual. The sociology of the intellectual world for Bourdieu is not so much a particular research specialty as an indispensable precondition for social scientific research. Reflexivity in this sense is a working method, recognizable in all of his various undertakings, whether they concern his research and teaching, the publishing of Liber and Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales, or his current activities in finding ways to redefine and revive the critical role of intellectuals.1 If, in contrast to this reflexive stance, there is anything lacking in Bourdieu’s writings, it is indeed the plain and spontaneous adherence to the established intellectual models. Bourdieu never quite identified himself with what was readily available, neither with the professorial fate of the academic specialist, nor with the Sartrean figure of the ‘total intellectual’. For a young French philosopher, originating from a province at about maximum distance from the capital, who had made it to the Ecole normale superieure, it was rather unusual, to say the least, to start ethnographic and sociological fieldwork in Algeria. Bourdieu’s subsequent work, marked by an unfailing refusal of the predominant dichotomies (theory/ research, objectivism/subjectivism, holism/individualism), testifies to the same unease with the primary divisions of the academic universe. His inability and unwillingness to be satisfied with the existing options is aptly illustrated by the dictum he quotes from Karl Krauss, the Viennese critic and writer: ‘Were I forced to choose between two evils, I would choose neither one’ (Bourdieu, 1997: 129). This inclination, visible in his way of constructing sentences and developing arguments, is at the root of acclaimed innovations in various research fields, and has, more generally, led him to conceive of social science as a reflexive endeavour. Bourdieu’s use of neither-nor reasoning is no rhetorical device, commonly employed to nestle oneself comfortably in the middle of two (often fictitious) extremes, but a way of gaining distance from the dominant views, allowing a reflection upon what is at stake for whom, and why some things are conceivable from one point of view, whereas others are not. This reflexive urge, which simultaneously questions a specific object and those who question the object in question, is present from his earliest work onwards. European Journal of Social Theory 2(3): 298–306
Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This paper argues for economic evaluators to have a less positivist attitude towards what is useful knowledge, and to use more imagination about the data and methodologies they use to increase the integrity and reliability of economic evaluations.

69 citations


Cites background from "Reflexivity and its Consequences"

  • ...…most difficult to acknowledge, and that not so much for technical but for social reasons, for reasons linked specifically to the scholastic view to which the inhabitants of the academic world tend to adhere without being conscious of it (Bourdieu, 1980; Bourdieu & Wacquant, 1992; Heilbron, 1999)....

    [...]

  • ...It is not the individual researcher who is of primary interest to Bourdieu, but rather the intellectual field as a whole (Bourdieu & Wacquant, 1992; Heilbron, 1999; Maton, 2003)....

    [...]

  • ...Second, reflexivity does not lead to a relativistic stance (Heilbron, 1999; Moatti et al., 1994)....

    [...]

  • ...…most objectivist tools of social science to become aware of the conditions of possibility (i.e., dispositions, strategies, limits, hidden assumptions, etc.) of the intellectual practice (Bourdieu, 1980, 2003; Bourdieu & Wacquant, 1992; Heilbron, 1999; Karakayali, 2004; Leander, 2002; Pels, 2000)....

    [...]

  • ...In the first instance, it does not undertake to explore the personal experiences of the researcher (Bourdieu, 1980, 2003; Bourdieu & Wacquant, 1992; Heilbron, 1999; Kenway & McLeod, 2004)....

    [...]

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The main purpose of as mentioned in this paper is to shed light on Pierre Bourdieu's conception of language, which is based on a number of ontological presuppositions, that is, a set of universal assumptions about the very nature of language.
Abstract: The main purpose of this paper is to shed light on Pierre Bourdieu’s conception of language. Although he has dedicated a significant part of his work to the study of language and even though his analysis of language has been extensively discussed in the literature, almost no attention has been paid to the fact that Bourdieu’s account of language is based on a number of ontological presuppositions, that is, on a set of universal assumptions about the very nature of language. This article aims to fill this gap in the literature by offering a detailed overview of 10 key features which, from a Bourdieusian point of view, can be regarded as inherent in language. On the basis of this enquiry, the study seeks to demonstrate that—contrary to common belief—there is not only a Bourdieusian sociology of language but also a Bourdieusian philosophy of language, which provides a useful theoretical framework for examining the unavoidable conditions of the real speech situation. The paper draws to a close by reflecting o...

63 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors draw on eighteen months of ethnographic fieldwork and my field diaries in refugee decision-making in Canada, and make three arguments in this article: the binary of research in closed vs. open settings may have contributed to overlooking of ethical challenges of research, and paying attention to "ethically important moments" during research practice may help us bridge the gap between principles of formal ethics and ethics in practice.
Abstract: By drawing on eighteen months of ethnographic fieldwork and my field diaries in refugee decision-making in Canada, I make three arguments in this article. First, the binary of research in closed vs. open settings may have contributed to overlooking of ethical challenges of research in state organizations in democratic settings. We have to overcome this binary by opening a dialogue among ethnographers. Second, despite well-developed and diverse nature of scholarship on Research Ethics' Board's (REB) formal practices and their negative impact on ethnographers' research proposals, the scarcity of scholarship on "ethics in practice" or "everyday ethics" show that we seem to forget that ethnographers, after receiving research ethics approval, still have to do considerable interpretation for what "being ethical" means. Finally, paying attention to "ethically important moments" during research practice may help us bridge the gap between principles of formal ethics and ethics in practice. Using field diaries in these reflections instead of more sanitized subsequent accounts illustrates the immediacy and importance of ethical concerns during research practice. URN: http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:0114-fqs150168

62 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: Bourdieu's reflexive sociology aims to undo these crippling effects as discussed by the authors, which presupposes a certain distance from the concerns of everyday life, which has both liberating and crippling effects.
Abstract: Scholarly activity presupposes a certain distance from the concerns of everyday life, which has both liberating and crippling effects. Bourdieu’s reflexive sociology hopes to undo these crippling e...

58 citations


Cites background from "Reflexivity and its Consequences"

  • ...More generally, Bourdieu’s work is often viewed as a meaningful alternative to the standard cognitive models and antinomies (e.g. objectivism-subjectivism; positivismrelativism) in the social sciences (Heilbron, 1999; Meisenhelder, 1997; Pels, 2000)....

    [...]

  • ...objectivism-subjectivism; positivismrelativism) in the social sciences (Heilbron, 1999; Meisenhelder, 1997; Pels, 2000)....

    [...]

01 Jan 2013
TL;DR: In this paper, a sociological critique of compatibilist metaphysics is presented, which is based on the notion of mutual attribution of responsibility and the universality of the belief in free will.
Abstract: Most contemporary political philosophies are underpinned by compatibilist metaphysics (which combines ontological determinism with practical free will). The present research is a sociological critique of its two major premises. The first premise defends the normative priority of democracy over philosophy: lay opinion enjoys full legitimacy to state what is feasible and what is not regarding principles of justice. The second premise is empirical and claims the universality of the belief in free will. The examination of this second premise begins with the acknowledgement of the limits of a moral sociology based on the mutual attribution of responsibility. From there, the program of a critical moral sociology is defined anew as aiming at the explanation of the social mechanisms that universalize the belief in free will and in responsibility. A quantitative study follows, comparing that belief as held by students in management with that of students in philosophy and with that of students in sociology. What emerges is that the contagion of some aspects of that belief is related to their social usefulness: part of that belief objectively stems from a dominant social position, yet it is subjectively perceived as its initial cause. It therefore appears that the injunction to moral responsibility attribution, as a mediator of legitimation of the established order, is much less the result of a "psychologizing neoliberal governmentality" than that of the functioning of any hierarchical social structure as a perpetual engine of production of inequalities. The true psychologization is that which, through the injunction to narcissistic display, increases an alleged need for social recognition, by disguising the demand that one conform to the dominant model as an invitation to being different from it, by turning an individual's narcissism into a most highly valued quality and, in the end, by strengthening the belief in the capacity of self-determination. Together, these two injunctions take part in the institution of free will.

52 citations

References
More filters
Book
01 Jan 1993

3,279 citations

Book
01 Jan 1990
TL;DR: Toulmin offers a radically new interpretation of Western intellectual history that humanizes our conception of modernity and reconciles the precision of scientific theory with the reality of human experience as discussed by the authors.
Abstract: Toulmin offers a radically new interpretation of Western intellectual history that humanizes our conception of modernity and reconciles the precision of scientific theory with the reality of human experience.

1,425 citations

Book
01 Jan 1998
TL;DR: A devastating critique of free-market politics from distinguished sociologist Pierre Bourdieu as mentioned in this paper is a classic example of such a critique. But it is also a critique of the free market.
Abstract: A devastating critique of free-market politics from distinguished sociologist Pierre Bourdieu.

791 citations