scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal Article

Some Questions of Moral Philosophy

01 Jan 1994-Social Research (New School University)-Vol. 61, Iss: 4, pp 739-764
TL;DR: In this paper, H. Arendt revient ici sur l'origine de la moralite, sur la question des valeurs et des principes modernes de l'action, que viennent contredire les horreurs hitleriennes et staliniennes d'une histoire encore proche.
Abstract: Publication de la conference introductive d'une serie de conferences donnees par H. Arendt a la Nouvelle Ecole de la Recherche Sociale a partir du 10 fevrier 1965. Avant de traiter de questions ethiques en relation avec la politique, la philosophie et la religion dans ses interventions futures, H. Arendt revient ici sur l'origine de la moralite, sur la question des valeurs et des principes modernes de l'action, que viennent contredire les horreurs hitleriennes et staliniennes d'une histoire encore proche

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Some Questions
of Moral
Philosophy
BY HANNAH ARENDT
After
the
publication,
in
1963,
oi
Eichmann
in
Jerusalem:
A
Report
on
the
Banality
of
Evil, Hannah Arendt's attention became
focused
on
moral
and
ethical questions.
On
February
10, 1965,
at
the New
School
for
Social Research,
she
initiated
a
series
of
lectures entitled "Some Questions
of
Moral Philosophy." What
follows is
the
introductory lecture, which,
in an
edited version,
is
published here
for the
first time.
The
subsequent lectures deal
with issues
in
ethics
and
politics, ethics
and
philosophy, ethics
and religion,
and
conclude with
a
consideration
of
judging
as
the connection between political
and
moral activity.
The
entire
lecture series will
be
published
in
Hannah
Arendt:
Essays
in
Understanding
1953-1975,
forthcoming from Harcourt Brace &
Company.
Jerome Kohn
JLJADIES AND GENTLEMEN. The
thoughts
of
many
of us, I
suppose, have wandered back during
the
last weeks
to
Winston
Spencer Churchill,
the
greatest statesman thus
far of our
century, who just died after
an
incredibly long life,
the
summit
of which
was
reached
at the
threshold
of old age.
This
happenstance,
if
such
it was,
like almost everything
he
stood
for
in his
convictions,
in his
writings,
in the
grand
but not
grandiose manner
of his
speeches, stood
in
conspicuous
contrast
to
whatever we
may
think
the
Zeitgeist
of
this
age to be.
It
is
perhaps this contrast that touches
us
most when
we
consider
his
greatness.
He has
been called
a
figure
of the
eighteenth century driven into
the
twentieth
as
though
the
Copyright
©
1994.
The
Hannah Arendt Literary Trust.
SOCIAL RESEARCH,
Vol. 61, No. 4
(Winter
1994)

740 SOCIAL RESEARCH
virtues of the past had taken over our destinies in their most
desperate crisis, and this, I think, is true as far as it goes. But
perhaps there is more to it. It is as though, in this shifting of
centuries, some permanent eminence of the human spirit
flashed up for an historically brief moment to show that
whatever makes for greatness—nobility, dignity, steadfastness,
and a kind of laughing courage—remains essentially the same
throughout the centuries.
Still, Churchill, so old-fashioned or, as I have suggested,
beyond the fashions of the times, was by no means unaware of
the decisive currents or undercurrents of the age in which he
lived. He wrote the following words about thirty years ago
when the true monstrosities of the century were yet unknown:
"Scarcely anything, material or established, which I was
brought up to believe was permanent and vital, has lasted.
Everything I was sure, or was taught to be sure, was impossible,
has happened." I wanted to mention these succinct words
which, alas, became fully true only some years after they were
uttered, in order to introduce, right at the beginning of these
lectures, the basic experiences which invariably lie behind or
beneath them. Among the many things which were still
thought to be "permanent and vital" at the beginning of the
century and yet have not lasted, I chose to turn our attention
to the moral issues, those which concern individual conduct
and behavior, the few rules and standards according to which
men used to tell right from wrong, and which were invoked to
judge or justify others and themselves, and whose validity were
supposed to be self-evident to every sane person either as a
part of divine or of natural law. Until, that is, without much
notice, all this collapsed almost overnight, and then it was as
though morality suddenly stood revealed in the original
meaning of the word, as a set of
mores,
customs and manners,
which could be exchanged for another set with hardly more
trouble than it would take to change the table manners of an
individual or a people. How strange and how frightening it
suddenly appeared that the very terms we use to designate

HANNAH ARENDT 741
these things—morality, with its Latin origin, and ethics, with its
Greek origin—should never have meant more than usages and
habits. And also that two thousand five hundred years of
thought, in literature, philosophy and religion, should not
have brought forth another word, notwithstanding all the
highfiown phrases, all assertions and preachings about the
existence of a conscience which speaks with an identical voice
to all men. What had happened? Did we finally awake from a
dream?
To be sure, a few had known before that there was
something wrong with this assumption of self-evidence for
moral commandments as though the "Thou shalt not bear
false testimony" could ever have the same validity as the
statement: two and two equal four. Nietzsche's quest for "new
values" certainly was a clear indication of the devaluation of
what his time called "values" and what former times more
correctly had called virtues. You remember that the only
standard he came up with was Life
itself,
and his criticism of
the traditional and essentially Christian virtues was guided by
the much more general insight that not only all Christian but
also all Platonic ethics use yardsticks and measurements which
are not derived from this world but from something beyond
it—be it the sky of ideas stretching over the dark cave of strictly
human affairs or the truly transcendent beyond of a divinely
ordained afterlife. Neitzsche called himself a moralist, and no
doubt he was; but to establish life as the highest good is
actually, so far as ethics are concerned, question-begging, since
all ethics, Christian or non-Christian, presuppose that life is not
the highest good for mortal men and that there is always more
at stake in life than the sustenance and procreation of
individual living organisms. That which is at stake may vary
greatly: it may be greatness and fame as in Pre-Socratic
Greece; it may be the permanence of the city as in Roman
virtue; it may be the health of the soul in this life, or the
salvation of the soul in the hereafter; and it may be freedom or
justice, or many more such things.

742 SOCIAL RESEARCH
Were these things or principles, from which all virtues are
ultimately derived, mere values which could be exchanged
against other values whenever people changed their minds
about them? And would they, as Nietzsche seems to indicate,
all go overboard before the overriding claim of Life itself? To
be sure, he could not have known that the existence of
mankind as a whole could ever be put into jeopardy by human
conduct, and in this marginal event one could indeed argue
that Life, the survival of the world and the human species, is
the highest good. But this would mean no more than that any
ethics or morality would simply cease to exist. And in principle
this thought was anticipated by the question implicit in the old
Latin saying. Fiat jvstitia, pereat mundus: Should the world
perish that justice be done? This question was answered by
Kant: "If justice perishes, human hfe on earth has lost its
meaning"
{"Wenn
die
Gerechtigkeit untergeht,
hat es
keinen Wert
mehr, dass Menschen
auf
Erden leben"). Hence,
the
only
new
moral principle, proclaimed in modern times, turns out to be
not the assertion of "new values" but the negation of morality
as such, although Nietzsche, of course, did not know this. And
it is his abiding greatness that he dared to demonstrate how
shabby and meaningless morality had become.
Churchill's words were uttered in the form of a statement,
but we, too full of the wisdom of hindsight, shall be tempted to
read them also as a premonition. And if it were just a question
of premonitions, I could indeed add an astounding number of
quotations which would go back at least to the first third of the
eighteenth century. The point of the matter for us, however, is
that we deal no longer with premonitions but with facts.
We—at least the older ones among us—have witnessed the
total collapse of all established moral standards in public and
private life during the 1930s and 40s, not only (as is now
usually assumed) in Hitler's Germany but also in Stalin's
Russia, where at this moment questions are being asked by the
younger generation that have a great resemblance to those
currently debated in Germany. Still, the differences between

HANNAH ARENDT 743
the two are significant enough to be mentioned. It has often
been noted that the Russian Revolution caused social upheaval
and social remolding of the entire nation unparalleled even in
the wake of Nazi Germany's radical fascist dictatorship, which,
it is true, left the property relation almost intact and did not
eliminate the dominant groups in society. From this, it usually
is concluded that what happened in the Third Reich was by
nature and not only by historical accident less permanent and
less extreme. This may or may not be true with respect to
strictly political developments, but it certainly is a fallacy if we
regard the issue of morality. Seen from a strictly moral
viewpoint, Stalin's crimes were, so to speak, old fashioned; like
an ordinary criminal, he never admitted them but kept them
surrounded in a cloud of hypocrisy and doubletalk while his
followers justified them as temporary means in the pursuit of
the "good" cause, or, if they happened to be a bit more
sophisticated, by the laws of history to which the revolutionary
has to submit and sacrifice himself if need be. Nothing in
Marxism, moreover, despite all the talk about "bourgeois
morality," announces a new set of moral values. If anything is
characteristic of Lenin or Trotsky as the representatives of the
professional revolutionary, it is the naive belief that once the
social circumstances are changed through revolution, mankind
will follow automatically the few moral precepts that have been
known and repeated since the dawn of history.
In this respect, the German developments are much more
extreme and perhaps also more revealing. There is not only
the gruesome fact of elaborately established death factories
and the utter absence of hypocrisy in those very substantial
numbers who were involved in the extermination program.
Equally important, but perhaps more frightening, was the
matter-of-course collaboration from all strata of German
society, including the older elites which the Nazis left
untouched, and who never identified themselves with the
party in power. I think it is justifiable on factual grounds to
maintain that morally, though not socially, the Nazi regime was

Citations
More filters
Book
Andreas Kalyvas1
01 Jan 2008
TL;DR: In this article, a theory of the extraordinary and political theory for the Republic of Councils has been proposed, which is based on the idea of the exception and constitutional politics of Carl Schmitt and Hannah Arendt.
Abstract: Preface: the extraordinary and political theory Part I. Charismatic Politics and the Symbolic Foundations of Power: Max Weber: 1. Revisiting Weber's concept of the political 2. Charismatic politics 3. Disavowing charismatic politics Part II. The Exception and Constitutional Politics: Carl Schmitt: 4. The popular constituent sovereign and the 'pure' theory of democratic legitimacy 5. Toward a theory of democratic constitutionalism 6. The extra-institutional sovereign Part III. Taming the Extraordinary: Hannah Arendt: 7. Extraordinary beginnings I: Arendt's critique of Schmitt 8. Extraordinary beginnings II: Arendt's response to Schmitt 9. The republic of councils: beyond democracy and liberalism? Conclusion: a democratic theory of the extraordinary Bibliography.

75 citations

Book
01 Jan 2012
TL;DR: The work of the French philosopher Michel Foucault is of key importance to this study and is used for elaborating a framework of ''technical mediation and subjectivation?''.
Abstract: The design of our own lives is about how technology guides and changes us. The book brings together converging trends in design theory and philosophy of technology concerning the mutual adaptation of technologies and humans. The aim is to contribute to the understanding of the impact of technology on us, to consider how this knowledge can be applied in design practice, as well as to discuss ethical questions about behavior guiding design. The book begins by discussing the themes of user guiding and changing technology in relation to design for usability. Next, the project is compared to the tradition of socially engaged and utopian design. The central part sets out philosophical and ethical research on the interrelations between humans and technology. The work of the French philosopher Michel Foucault is of key importance to this study and is used for elaborating a framework of `technical mediation and subjectivation?. In this approach, technology is not set in opposition to human freedom and morality; rather coping with the influences of technology is seen as part of becoming a moral subject. The ethics of technology developed after Foucault focuses on care for the quality of our interactions and fusions with technology. Hybridization is central to the approach: it is not to be rejected, neither is it the greatest danger, but it does deserve the greatest care. We are called upon to care for the design of our own lives. The book contains a variety of examples. A case study about the RFID public transport e?paying system in the Netherlands (OV chip card), for instance, serves to illustrate how social and ethical aspects ? from usability to privacy and security issues ? can be assessed from the perspective of product impact on users.

59 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors argue that the possibility of inscription is indeed thematized in Ranciere's more historical writings, but is often ignored by commentators, and draw out the implications of a focus on inscription for democratic theory and practice.
Abstract: Democratic theory is often portrayed as torn between two moments: that of disruption of rule, and the ordinary, ongoing institutionalization of politics. This dualism also marks contemporary democratic theory. In Jacques Ranciere's theory of politics it takes the form of an emphasis on the ruptural qualities of the staging of novel democratic demands and the reconfiguration of the space of political argument. The reconfiguration of existing political imaginaries depends upon a moment of inscription, which remains underdeveloped in Ranciere's work. Arguing that the possibility of inscription is indeed thematized in Ranciere's more historical writings, but is often ignored by commentators, this article seeks to draw out the implications of a focus on inscription for democratic theory and practice. To flesh out this account, the article draws on Cavell's writings on exemplarity and the role of exemplars in fostering both critical reflection and the imagination of alternatives. The focus on such exemplars and an aversive, nonconformist ethos together facilitate a better understanding of what is required for such novel demands to be acknowledged and inscribed into democratic life.

52 citations

Book
17 Apr 2013
TL;DR: The case for moral relativism is not an argument; it's a pair of observations as mentioned in this paper : people live and have lived by mutually incompatible moral norms, and no one has ever succeeded in showing any one set of norms to be universally valid.
Abstract: I am not going to argue for moral relativism. The case for moral relativism is not an argument; it’s a pair of observations. The first observation is that people live and have lived by mutually incompatible moral norms. The second observation is that no one has ever succeeded in showing any one set of norms to be universally valid. These observations do not prove that there is no universally valid morality, but they do lead us to wonder: If there weren’t a universally valid morality, would th...

44 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: A key problem for critical theory is how to problematize the very concepts that undergird its own frameworks once they have become canonical as mentioned in this paper, and the more that certain constructs come to dominate an in...
Abstract: A key problem for critical theory is how to problematize the very concepts that undergird its own frameworks once they have become canonical. The more that certain constructs come to dominate an in...

43 citations


Cites background from "Some Questions of Moral Philosophy"

  • ...It interrupts action, no matter what one is doing (Arendt, 2003: 164)....

    [...]

  • ...I turn to two essays, ‘Thinking and Moral Considerations’ (Arendt, 2003), and ‘Some Questions of Moral Philosophy’ (Arendt, 2003) written after her controversial book Eichmann in Jerusalem (Arendt, 1963) appeared....

    [...]

References
More filters
Book
10 Apr 2021
TL;DR: Werner Pluhar's translation of Kant's Critique of Practical Reason as mentioned in this paper meets the standards set in his widely respected translations of the Critique and Pure Reason.
Abstract: With this volume, Werner Pluhar completes his work on Kant's three Critiques, an accomplishment unique among English language translators of Kant. At once accurate, fluent, and accessible, Pluhar's rendition of the Critique of Practical Reason meets the standards set in his widely respected translations of the Critique of Judgment (1987) and the Critique of Pure Reason (1996). Stephen Engstrom's Introduction discusses the place of the second Critique in Kant's critical philosophy, its relation to Kant's ethics, and its practical purpose and provides an illuminating outline of Kant's argument.

1,623 citations

Book
01 Oct 2015
TL;DR: The Critique of Practical Reason as mentioned in this paper criticizes the entire practical faculty of reason, including the pure faculty itself, in order to see whether reason in making such a claim does not presumptuously overstep itself (as is the case with speculative reason).
Abstract: This work is called the Critique of Practical Reason, not of the pure practical reason, although its parallelism with the speculative critique would seem to require the latter term The reason of this appears sufficiently from the treatise itself Its business is to show that there is pure practical reason, and for this purpose it criticizes the entire practical faculty of reason If it succeeds in this, it has no need to criticize the pure faculty itself in order to see whether reason in making such a claim does not presumptuously overstep itself (as is the case with the speculative reason) For if, as pure reason, it is actually practical, it proves its own reality and that of its concepts by fact, and all disputation against the possibility of its being real is futile

1,449 citations

Book
01 Jan 1969
TL;DR: Foundations of the Metaphysics of MoralsQuine, New Foundations, and the Philosophy of Set TheoryThe Foundation of Reality Foundations of RealityFoundation of Reality: Grounding for the META of MorALSMoral Law: Groundwork of the METAPHysics of Moral LawThe Moral Law and the Moral Law's Groundwork as mentioned in this paper.
Abstract: Foundations of the Metaphysics of MoralsQuine, New Foundations, and the Philosophy of Set TheoryThe Foundation of RealityFoundations of the Metaphysics of MoralsMoral Law: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of MoralsFoundations of the Philosophy of ValueKant's ProlegomenaFundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of MoralsRelativism and the Foundations of PhilosophyMetaphysics as FoundationPlato on the Metaphysical Foundation of Meaning and TruthKant: Metaphysical Foundations of Natural ScienceThe Moral LawGrounding for the Metaphysics of MoralsCritique of JudgementKant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of MoralsFundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of MoralsFoundations of the Metaphysics of MoralsImmanuel Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of MoralsAristotle's RevengeContemporary Readings in the Foundations of MetaphysicsGroundwork for the Metaphysics of MoralsThe Philosophy of KantKant and the Foundations of MoralityThe Ant TrapKant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of MoralsThe Metaphysic of EthicsThe Foundations of NatureFundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of EthicsFoundations for a Metaphysics of Pure ProcessThe Foundations of Metaphysics in ScienceKant's Construction of NatureEntity and IdentityThe metaphysical foundations of modern physical sciencePhilosophy of PhysicsThe Metaphysical Foundations of LogicVarieties of ThingsHegel’s Foundation Free MetaphysicsTheoretical Philosophy after 1781Moral Foundations of Philosophy of Mind

1,279 citations