scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Journal ArticleDOI

The Optimum Enforcement of Laws

01 May 1970-Journal of Political Economy (The University of Chicago Press)-Vol. 78, Iss: 3, pp 55-67
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors construct a theory of rational enforcement, a theory which owes much to Gary Becker's major article on the subject (1968), and construct a model for the costs of enforcing various kinds of contracts.
Abstract: All prescriptions of behavior for individuals require enforcement. Usually the obligation to behave in a prescribed way is entered into voluntarily by explicit or implicit contract. For example, I promise to teach certain classes with designated frequency and to discuss matters which I, and possibly others, believe are relevant to the course titles. By negotiation, and in the event of its failure, by legal action, I and my employer seek to enforce the contract of employment against large departures from the promised behavior. Performance of some kinds of behavior is difficult or impossible to enforce-such as promises to be creative, noble, or steadfast in crisis-and as a result such contractual promises are either not made or enforced only when there is an uncontroversially flagrant violation. The influence upon contract, and upon economic organization generally, of the costs of enforcing various kinds of contracts has received virtually no study by economists, despite its immense potential explanatory power. When the prescribed behavior is fixed unilaterally rather than by individual agreement, we have the regulation or law, and enforcement of these unilateral rules is the subject of the present essay. Departures of actual from prescribed behavior are crimes or violations, although one could wish for a less formidable description than "criminal" to describe many of the trifling offenses or the offenses against unjust laws. My primary purpose is to construct a theory of rational enforcement, a theory which owes much to Gary Becker's major article on the subject (1968). In the conclusion the problem of explanation, as distinguished from prescription, will be commented upon.

Summary (2 min read)

I. THE GOAL OF ENFORCEMENT

  • The goal of enforcement, let us assume, is to achieve that degree of compliance with the rule of prescribed (or proscribed) behavior that the society believes it can afford.
  • There is one decisive reason why the society must forego "complete" enforcement of the rule: enforcement is costly.
  • The authors could make certain that crime does not pay by paying enough to apprehend most criminals.
  • It may be that in a few offenses some gain to the offender is viewed as a gain to society,' but such social gains seem too infrequent, small, and capricious to put an effective limitation upon the size of punishments.
  • The owner of large properties is required to do much of his direct policing: there are surely more watchmen and guards than policemen in a typical city.

II. THE SUPPLY OF OFFENSES 59

  • A consumption offense would be illustrated by speeding in an automobile used for recreation or assaulting a courtship rival (when the girl is poor).
  • It is only under the shelter of the civil magistrate that the owner of that valuable property, which is acquired by the labour of many years, or perhaps of many successive generations, can sleep a single night in security.
  • One must choose the locality of maximum income expectation (and perhaps, like a salesman, move from area to area).
  • The probability of apprehension (and therefore of conviction) is an increasing function of the frequency of commission of offenses.
  • The costs of production of the offenses are the ordinary outlays of offenders plus the penalties imposed by the society.

111. THE ENFORCEMENT AGENCY: A NORMATIVE APPROACH

  • The penalty structure should incorporate the social appraisal of the importance of the suppression of the offenses.
  • The law does not in general provide this scale of values, as can be shown by the list of maximum penalties for the violations of economic regulations listed in Table I .
  • The penalties for the essentially similar offense (if such it must be called) of reducing freight rates can be ten times as much for a barge operator as for a trucker.
  • One may conjecture that two features of punishment of traditional criminal law have been carried over to economic regulation: the attribution of a substantial cost to the act of conviction itself, and the related belief that moral guilt does not vary closely with the size of the offense.
  • Whatever the source, the penalty structure is not well designed for either deterrence or guidance of enforcement.

IV. CONCLUSION

  • The widespread failure to adopt rational criteria of enforcement of laws has been due often and perhaps ustially.
  • To a simple lack of understanding of the need for and nature of rational enforcement.
  • The appropriations to the enforcement agency and the verdicts of juries are the instruments by which the community may constantly review public policy.
  • There is considerable inertia in the legislative 6.
  • The peculiarities of the structure of sanctions in economic regulation are partially due also to the response of the regulated businesses.

Did you find this useful? Give us your feedback

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

This PDF is a selection from an out-of-print volume from the National
Bureau of Economic Research
Volume Title: Essays in the Economics of Crime and Punishment
Volume Author/Editor: Gary S. Becker and William M. Landes, eds.
Volume Publisher: NBER
Volume ISBN: 0-87014-263-1
Volume URL: http://www.nber.org/books/beck74-1
Publication Date: 1974
Chapter Title: The Optimum Enforcement of Laws
Chapter Author: George J. Stigler
Chapter URL: http://www.nber.org/chapters/c3626
Chapter pages in book: (p. 55 - 67)

APPROACH
nt Legislation on the
[issertation, Columbia
The
Optimum Enforcement
York:
Macmillan Co.,
nts
for
Inventions."
of
Laws
Lou'. Vol. II. 2d ed.
uinistration of Justice.
George
J. Stigler
ton: U.S. Government
University of Chicago and National Bureau of Economic Research
on: U.S. Government
Ion: U.S. Government
Lk
Force
ts.") Washington: U.S.
rs A dnuinisirationfroin
," in
President's Corn-
All prescriptions of behavior for individuals require enforcement.
of Justice. Organized
Usually the obligation to behave in a prescribed way is entered into
Government Printing
voluntarily by explicit or implicit contract. For example, I promise to
teach certain classes with designated frequency and to discuss matters
Back Up the Police."
which I, and possibly others, believe are relevant to the course titles. By
negotiation, and in the event of its failure, by legal action, I and my em-
alysis." MA. thesis,
ployer seek to enforce the contract of employment against large depar-
tures from the promised behavior. Performance of some kinds of behavior
Case of Electncity."
is difficult or impossible to enforce—such as promises to be creative,
noble, or steadfast in crisis—and as a result such contractual promises
conomy 72 (February
.
are
either not made or enforced only when there is an uncontroversially
Journa! of Laui'
and
flagrant violation. The influence upon contract, and upon economic
organization generally, of the costs of enforcing various kinds of contracts
adelphia: J. B. Lippin-
has received virtually no study by economists, despite its immense poten-
tial explanatory power.
When the prescribed behavior is fixed unilaterally rather than by indi-
vidual agreement, we have the regulation or law, and enforcement of
these unilateral rules is the subject of the present essay. Departures of
actual from prescribed behavior are crimes or violations, although one
could wish for a less formidable description than "criminal" to describe

56
THE OPTIMUM ENFORCEMENT OF LAWS
many of the trifling offenses or the offenses against unjust laws. My
primary purpose is to construct a theory of rational enforcement, a theory
which owes much to Gary Becker's major article on the subject (1968). in
the conclusion the problem of explanation, as distinguished from prescrip-
tion, will be commented upon.
I. THE GOAL OF ENFORCEMENT
The goal of enforcement, let us assume, is to achieve that degree of com-
pliance with the rule of prescribed (or proscribed) behavior that the
society believes it can afford. There is one decisive reason why the so-
ciety must forego "complete" enforcement of the rule: enforcement is
costly.
The extent of enforcement of laws depends upon the amount of re-
sources devoted to the task. With enough policemen, almost every speed-
ing automobile could be identified. The success of tenacious pursuit of
the guilty in celebrated crimes (such as the great English train robbery
and the assassination of Martin King) suggests that few crimes of sane
men could escape detection. We could make certain that crime does not
pay by paying enough to apprehend most criminals. Such a level of en-
forcement would of course he enormously expensive, and only in crimes
of enormous importance will such expenditures be approached. The
society will normally give to the enforcement agencies a budget which
dictates a much lower level of enforcement.
The cost limitation upon the enforcement of laws would prevent the
society from forestalling, detecting, and punishing all offenders, but it
would appear that punishments which would be meted out to the guilty
could often be increased without using additional resources. The offender
is deterred by the expected punishment, which is (as a first approxima-
tion) the probability of punishment times the punishment—$ 100 if the
probability of conviction is 1/10 and the fine $1,000. Hence, increasing
the punishment would seem always to increase the deterrence. Capital
punishment is cheaper than long term imprisonment; and seizure of all
the offender's property may not be much more expensive than collecting
a more moderate fine.
To escape from this conclusion, Becker introduces as a different limi-
tation on punishment the "social value of the gain to offenders" from the
offense. The determination of this social value is not explained, and one
is entitled to doubt its usefulness as an explanatory concept: what evi-
dence is there that society sets a positive value upon the utility derived
from a murder, rape, or arson? In fact the society has branded the utility
derived from such act
gain to the offender i:
seem too infrequent,
upon the size of puni
Instead we take
ment, which arises o
doubt true that the
pected netutility to
given offense. But
of life, and the margi
small or even
sault and for a murdc
thief has his hand cu
$5,000. Marginal c
marginal deterrence
otherwise appropriat
One special asp
need to avoid overe
apprehend most guil
and frequent convic
system, there will in I
parties, and these ml
and loss of confidei
defense of innocent p
are part of the costs
viction of innocent p
marginal deterrence I
The significance
that will be used to
the gravity of the ofi
manifest itself only i
more tenaciously th
I. For example, the I
warms
the neighboring ho
2. Becker writes the I
where Y is the money val
f the fine. (The income,
single offense Y must be
spect to
Y, =
tive for all
}'. Of course
crime.

LAWS
GEORGE J. STIGLER
57
inst unjust laws. My
enforcement, a theory
the subject (1968). In
from prescrip-
'e that degree of corn-
behavior that the
ie reason why the so-
rule: enforcement is
the amount of re-
!n, almost every speed-
tenacious pursuit of
English train robbery
few crimes of sane
that crime does not
Such a level of en-
ye, and only in crimes
be approached. The
ncies a budget which
ws would prevent the
all offenders, but it
eted out to the guilty
sources. The offender
(as a first approxima-
ishment—$ 100 if the
)O. Hence, increasing
e deterrence. Capital
nt; and seizure of all
ensive than collecting
ces as a different limi-
o offenders" from the
at explained, and one
y concept: what evi-
on the utility derived
as branded the utility
derived from such activities as illicit. It may be that in a few offenses some
gain to the offender is viewed as a gain to society,' but such social gains
seem too infrequent, small, and capricious to put an effective limitation
upon the size of punishments.
Instead we take account of another source of limitation of punish-
ment, which arises out of the nature of the supply of offenses. It is no
doubt true that the larger the punishment, the smaller will be the ex-
pected net utility to the prospective offender from the commission of a
given offense. But marginal decisions are made here as in the remainder
of life, and the marginal deterrence of heavy punishments could be very
small or even negative. If the offender will be executed for a minor as-
sault and for a murder, there is no marginal deterrence to murder. if the
thief has his hand cut off for taking five dollars, he had just as well take
$5,000. Marginal costs are necessary to marginal deterrence.2 The
marginal deterrence to committing small crimes is also distorted if an
otherwise appropriate schedule of penalties is doubled or halved.
One special aspect of this cost limitation upon enforcement is the
need to avoid overenforcement. The enforcement agency could easily
apprehend most guilty people if we placed no limits upon the charging
and frequent conviction of innocent people. in any real enforcement
system, there will in fact be conviction and punishment of some innocent
parties, and these miscarriages of justice impose costs of both resources
and loss of confidence in the enforcement machinery. The costs of
defense of innocent parties, whether borne by themselves or by the state,
are part of the costs of enforcement from the social viewpoint. The con-
viction of innocent persons encourages the crime because it reduces the
marginal deterrence to its commission.
The significance of an offense to society
the quantity of resources
that will be used to "prevent" the offense—will in general increase with
the gravity of the offense. The increase in resources, however, will not
manifest itself only in an increase in punishments. The state will pursue
more tenaciously the offender who commits a larger crime (or repeti-
1. For example, the thief reduces the welfare expenditures of the state, or the arsonist
warms the neighboring houses.
2. Becker writes the expected utility from an offense as EU=pU(Y—f)+(l
—p)U(Y),
where
Y is the money value of the gain, p the probability of detection and conviction, and
f the fine. (The income, Y, and fine,f, must be interpreted as average annual flows; for a
single offense Y must be less than f.) If
this expression is differentiated partially with re-
spect
to
Y,
—p)U'(Y)
U'(Y)—pfU'(Y), which
is
posi-
tive for all Y.
Of
course p and f
will
increase with Y to
prevent this incitement to larger
crime.

58
THE OPTIMUM ENFORCEMENT OF LAWS
tive crimes) and thus increase also the probability of apprehending him.
There is a division of labor between the state and the citizen in the
prevention of virtually every offense. The owner of large properties is
required to do much of his direct policing: there are surely more watch-
men and guards than policemen in a typical city. The larger accumula-
tions of wealth, moreover, are to be guarded by the owner through devices
such as nonnegotiability and custody of funds by specialists. Accordingly,
the pub/ic
punishments
for crimes against property do not increase in
proportion to the value of the property. In the protection of people, as
distinguished from their property, the individual is required to protect
himself from minor offenses or at least to detect their occurrence and
assume a large part of the burden of prosecution (for example, shop-
lifting, insults, simple trespass), but he is allowed less discretion in prose-
cution for major assaults.
The relationship of duration and nature of penalties to age and sex of
offender, frequency of previous offenses, and so forth is also explicable
in terms of cost of enforcement. The first-time offender may have com-
mitted the offense almost accidentally and (given any punishment) with
negligible probability of repetition, so heavy penalties (which have
substantial costs to the state) are unnecessary. The probability of a rep-
etition of an offense by a seasoned offender is also zero during his
imprisonment, so the probability of repetition of an offense is relevant
to the penalty also in his case.
Indeed, the problem of determining the efficient penalty may be
viewed as one in statistical inference: to estimate the individual's average,
durable propensity to offend (the population value) on the basis of a
sample of his observed behavior and how this propensity responds to
changes in penalties. As in other sequential sampling problems, one can
estimate this propensity more accurately, the longer the individual's
behavior is observed.
The society will be more concerned (because each individual is more
concerned) with major than minor offenses in the foUowing sense: there
is increasing marginal disutility of offenses, so a theft of $1,000 is more
than twice as harmful as a theft of $500. In the area of offenses to prop-
erty, this result is implied by diminishing marginal utility of income. In
the area of offenses to persons, it is more difficult to measure damage in
any direct way, but a similar rule probably holds.
So much for prevention and punishment; let us turn to the offenses.
II. THE SUPPLY
The commission of ol
act of consumption.
speeding in an autorr
rival (when the girl
i
by theft, smuggling,
realm of offenses to p
and we may recall A
crime:
The affluence of the nc
driven by want, and prc
the shelter of the civil r
is acquired by the
tions, can sleep a singi
known enemies, whom
from whose injustice h
magistrate continually
extensive property, th
government. Where the
of two or three days a
p. 670).
The professiona
of occupational choi
expected returns an'
difference with the i
legitimate activities.
correspond to the c
injuries to a
of apprehen
cupations have only
The details of o'
from those encounte
the locality of maxir
man, move from
ar
in
periods of(involui
can be expected to

Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, a Bayesian approach to hypothesis testing, model selection, and accounting for model uncertainty is presented, which is straightforward through the use of the simple and accurate BIC approximation, and it can be done using the output from standard software.
Abstract: It is argued that P-values and the tests based upon them give unsatisfactory results, especially in large samples. It is shown that, in regression, when there are many candidate independent variables, standard variable selection procedures can give very misleading results. Also, by selecting a single model, they ignore model uncertainty and so underestimate the uncertainty about quantities of interest. The Bayesian approach to hypothesis testing, model selection, and accounting for model uncertainty is presented. Implementing this is straightforward through the use of the simple and accurate BIC approximation, and it can be done using the output from standard software. Specific results are presented for most of the types of model commonly used in sociology. It is shown that this approach overcomes the difficulties with P-values and standard model selection procedures based on them. It also allows easy comparison of nonnested models, and permits the quantification of the evidence for a null hypothesis of interest, such as a convergence theory or a hypothesis about societal norms.

6,100 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, a theory of participation in illegitimate activities is developed and tested against data on variations in index crimes across states in the United States and behavioral implications are derived using the state preference approach to behavior under uncertainty.
Abstract: A theory of participation in illegitimate activities is developed and tested against data on variations in index crimes across states in the United States. Theorems and behavioral implications are derived using the state preference approach to behavior under uncertainty. The investigation deals directly with the interaction between offense and defense: crime and collective law enforcement. It indicates the existence of a deterrent effect of law-enforcement activity on all crimes and a strong positive correlation between income inequality and crimes against property. The empirical results also provide some tentative estimates of the effectiveness of law enforcement in reducing crime and the resulting social losses.

1,871 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors consider the problem of accounting for model uncertainty in linear regression models and propose two alternative approaches: the Occam's window approach and the Markov chain Monte Carlo approach.
Abstract: We consider the problem of accounting for model uncertainty in linear regression models. Conditioning on a single selected model ignores model uncertainty, and thus leads to the underestimation of uncertainty when making inferences about quantities of interest. A Bayesian solution to this problem involves averaging over all possible models (i.e., combinations of predictors) when making inferences about quantities of interest. This approach is often not practical. In this article we offer two alternative approaches. First, we describe an ad hoc procedure, “Occam's window,” which indicates a small set of models over which a model average can be computed. Second, we describe a Markov chain Monte Carlo approach that directly approximates the exact solution. In the presence of model uncertainty, both of these model averaging procedures provide better predictive performance than any single model that might reasonably have been selected. In the extreme case where there are many candidate predictors but ...

1,804 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This article extended the traditional theory of individual rational choice to analyze social issues beyond those usually considered by economists and incorporated into the theory a much richer class of attitudes, preferences, and calculations.
Abstract: An important step in extending the traditional theory of individual rational choice to analyze social issues beyond those usually considered by economists is to incorporate into the theory a much richer class of attitudes, preferences, and calculations. While this approach to behavior builds on an expanded theory of individual choice, it is not mainly concerned with individuals. It uses theory at the micro level as a powerful tool to derive implications at the group or macro level. The lecture describes the approach and illustrates it with examples drawn from my past and current work.

1,407 citations

DOI
18 Dec 2014

1,339 citations

References
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In fact, some common properties are shared by practically all legislation, and these properties form the subject matter of this essay as discussed by the authors, which is the basis for this essay. But, in spite of such diversity, some commonsense properties are not shared.
Abstract: Since the turn of the twentieth century, legislation in Western countries has expanded rapidly to reverse the brief dominance of laissez faire during the nineteenth century. The state no longer merely protects against violations of person and property through murder, rape, or burglary but also restricts ‘discrimination’ against certain minorities, collusive business arrangements, ‘jaywalking’, travel, the materials used in construction, and thousands of other activities. The activities restricted not only are numerous but also range widely, affecting persons in very different pursuits and of diverse social backgrounds, education levels, ages, races, etc. Moreover, the likelihood that an offender will be discovered and convicted and the nature and extent of punishments differ greatly from person to person and activity to activity. Yet, in spite of such diversity, some common properties are shared by practically all legislation, and these properties form the subject matter of this essay.

9,613 citations