scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Book

Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Volume 5: 1884-1886

01 Dec 1993-
TL;DR: The Herbartian view of the human mind has been criticised by as discussed by the authors, who pointed out that if there is no tendency for natural ideas to be true, there can be no hope of ever reaching true inductions and hypotheses.
Abstract: ly considered, a system of like parabolas similarly placed, or any one of an infinity of systems of curves, is as simple as the system of straight lines. Again, motions and forces are combined according to the principle of the parallelogram, and a parallelogram appears to us a very simple figure. Yet the whole system of parallelograms is no more simple than any relief-perspective of them, or than any one of an infinity of other systems. As Sir Isaac Newton well said, geometry is but a branch of mechanics. No definition of the straight line is possible except that it is the path of a particle undisturbed by any force; and no definitions of parallels, etc. are possible which do not depend upon the definition of equal distances as measured by a rigid body, or other mechanical means. Thus, in dynamics, the natural ideas of the human mind tend to approximate to the truth of nature, because the mind has been formed under the influence of dynamical laws. Now, logical considerations show that if there is no tendency for natural ideas to be true, there can be no hope of ever reaching true inductions and hypotheses. So that philosophy is committed to the postulate,—without which it has no chance of success,—[. . .] Psychology has only lately become a positive science, and in my humble opinion the new views are now carried too far. I cannot see, for example, why psychologists should make such a bugbear of “faculties.” If in dynamics it has proved safe to rely upon our natural ideas, checked, controlled, and corrected by experience, why should not our natural ideas about mind, formed as they certainly have been under the influence of the true laws of mental action, be likely to approximate to the truth as much as natural ideas of space, force, and the like have been found to do? Upon this point, I must confess to entertaining somewhat heterodox opinions. The Herbartian philosophy, with the mode of reasoning which leads to it, seems to me thoroughly unsound and illusory,—though I fully admit the value and profundity of some of the suggestions of that philosophy. But to trust to such reasoning in the slightest degree seems to me ever so much less safe than trusting to one’s native or natural notions about mind, though these no doubt need to be modified by observation and experiment. For my part it seems to me that the elementary phenomena of mind fall into three categories. First, we have feelings, comprising all that is immediately present, such as pleasure and pain, blue, cheerfulness, and the feeling which arises upon the contemplation of a complete theory. It is hard to define what I mean by feeling. If I say it is what is present, I W r i t i n g s o f C . S . P e i r c e 1 8 9 0 – 1 8 9 2 96 shall be asked what I mean by present, and must confess I mean nothing but feeling again. The only way is to state how any state of consciousness is to be modified so as to render it a feeling, although feeling does not essentially involve consciousness proper. But imagine a state of consciousness reduced to perfect simplicity, so that its object is entirely unanalyzed, then that consciousness reduced to that rudimentary condition, unattainable by us, would be a pure feeling, and not properly consciousness at all. Let the quality of blue, for example, override all other ideas, of form, of contrast, of commencement or cessation, and there would be pure feeling. When I say that such impossible states exist as elements of all consciousness, I mean that there are ideas which might conceivably thus exist alone and monopolize the whole mind. Besides feelings, we have in our minds sensations of reaction, as when a person blindfold suddenly runs against a post, when we make a muscular effort, or when any feeling gives way to another feeling. Suppose I had nothing in my mind but a feeling of blue, which were suddenly to give place to a feeling of red; then, at the instant of transition there would be a sense of reaction, my blue life being transmuted to red life. If I were now also endowed with a memory, that sense would continue for some time. This state of mind would be more than pure feeling, since in addition to the feeling of red a feeling analogous to blue would be present, and not only that but a sense of reaction between the two. This sense of reaction would itself carry along with it a peculiar feeling which might conceivably monopolize the mind to the exclusion of the feelings of blue and red. But were this to happen, though the feeling associated with a sense of reaction would be there, the sense of reaction as such would be quite gone; for a sense of reaction cannot conceivably exist independent of at least two feelings between which the reaction takes place. A feeling, then, is a state of mind having its own living quality, independent of any other. A sense of reaction, or say for short a sensation, is a state of mind containing two states of mind between which we are aware of a connection, even if that connection is no more than a contrast. No analysis can reduce such sensations to feelings. Looking at the matter from a physiological point of view, a feeling only calls for an excited nerve-cell,—or indeed a mere mass of excited nerve-matter without any cell, or shut up in any number of cells. But sensation supposes the discharge or excitation of a nerve-cell, or a transfer of excitement from one part of a mass of nerve-matter to another, or the spontaneous production or cessation of an excited condition. 22. Architecture of Theories. Initial Version, 1890 97 Besides feelings and sensations, we have general conceptions; that is, we are conscious that a connection between feelings is determined by a general rule; or, looking at the matter from another point of view, a general conception is the being aware of being governed by a habit. Intellectual power is simply facility in taking habits and in following them in cases essentially analogous to, but in non-essentials widely remote from, the normal cases of sensation, or connection of feelings, under which those habits were formed. The one primordial law of mental action is a tendency to generalization; that is, every connection between feelings tends to spread to neighboring feelings. If you ask what are neighboring feelings, it is like the question that was answered by the parable of the Good Samaritan. A neighboring feeling is simply a connected feeling. These connections are of two kinds, internal or manifest, and external or occult. A feeling is manifestly connected with feelings which it resembles or contrasts with; the connection is merely an identity of feeling. A feeling is occultly connected with feelings bound to it by some external power, as the roll of thunder with the flash of lightning. The mental law belongs to a widely different category of law from physical laws. A physical law determines that a certain component motion must take place, otherwise the law is violated. But such absolute conformity is not required by the mental law. It does not call for any definite amount of assimilation in any case. Indeed such a precise regulation would be in downright conflict with the law. For it would instantly crystallize thought and prevent all further formation of habit. The law of mind makes something the more likely to happen. It thus resembles the “non-conservative” forces of physics, such as viscosity and the like, which are due to chance encounters of molecules.
Citations
More filters
Book
01 Jan 1962

112 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, it is impossible not to be aware of the derivative character of some of the language of Lowell's "Ode Recited at the Harvard Commemoration" and the influence of Milton in such phrases as high emprise and ethereal essence.
Abstract: IT is impossible not to be aware of the derivative character of some of the language of Lowell's "Ode Recited at the Harvard Commemoration." The influence of Milton, for example, is clearly evident in such phrases as high emprise and ethereal essence. Words like guerdon, sear (as a homonym, hard upon the heels of laurels in both "Lycidas" and the "Commemoration Ode"), mantle, and reck not reveal the extent to which Lowell has absorbed the vocab-

4 citations

References
More filters
Journal Article
TL;DR: In the last few years several more articles on this subject have been written, each filling in a gap left by the others: Ayers' is a theological view, based solely on the Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (CP) ; later articles fill out Pece's mathematics and his logic; and as discussed by the authors attempts to fill in a genealogical gap by showing how his thought on miracles is directly related to his dialogues with Plato, Hume and Lutoslawski.
Abstract: Twenty-three years ago Robert Ayers noticed several brief and intriguing comments on miracles in the Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (CP) . Working with just those scraps of information from the CP, he stitched together a rough but helpful starting point for understanding this aspect of Peirce's religious and scientific thought. In the last few years several more articles on this subject have been written, each filling in a gap left by the others: Ayers' is a theological view, based solely on the CP ; later articles fill out Peirce's mathematics and his logic. This paper attempts to fill in a genealogical gap by showing how his thought on miracles is directly related to his dialogues with Plato, Hume, and Lutoslawski. My resources are largely unpublished manuscripts, many of which are fragmentary. I show the relationship between these manuscripts and two key published essays, "Philosophy and the Conduct of Life" (1898), and "On the Logic of Drawing History from Ancient Documents, Especially from Testimonies" (1901), and then show how Peirce, in dialogue with Plato, exposes and overcomes the nominalistic and anti-miracle prejudices of historiography in his day. The resulting view of history is fallibilistic, realistic and evolutionary, in which miracles are not violations of laws of nature but are to be expected as evolutionary variations that form part of the ongoing self-revelation of the cosmos. Miracles, like all events in history, must not be viewed prejudicially by adherents or detractors, but must be taken into careful account in the grand induction of history and science.

2 citations

26 Nov 2013
TL;DR: Palavras-chave et al. as mentioned in this paper consider the human mind equipped with this inferential process dealing with the acquisition of knowledge without taking psychological aspects into consideration, and establish the principles that ground the existence of a substrate of the same nature between the cognizant and the cognizable, in such way the acquired product, that is, the knowledge established in the form of a thought not be reduced to a human mental creation.
Abstract: Resumo: No que compete a Historia da Logica, podemos divisar dois tipos de logicos, a saber: aqueles que se valem de principios psicologicos para o raciocinio e aqueles que nao se valem de tais principios. Charles S. Peirce pertenceu ao segundo grupo e, sobre o referido assunto, ele possuia determinada posicao da qual nunca mudou de opiniao, embora esta somente tenha se consolidado em sua maturidade quando estatuiu a sua Classificacao das Ciencias. Neste artigo, nao lidaremos com esse Peirce maduro cujas concepcoes filosoficas ja estao consolidadas. Nossa pesquisa abordara as raizes de sua filosofia, principalmente quanto a sua concepcao do processo inferencial. Embora possa parecer um tema caracteristico de Logica, a questao que nos propomos e considerar como a mente humana munida do processo inferencial lida com a aquisicao de conhecimento sem levar em consideracao os aspectos psicologicos. Assim, partindo-se do pressuposto do aspecto nao psicologico atribuido a logica, procuraremos estabelecer os principios que fundamentam a existencia de um substrato de mesma natureza entre o conhecedor e o conhecido, de maneira que o produto adquirido, isto e, o conhecimento estabelecido na forma de um pensamento nao se reduza a uma criacao mental humana. Palavras-chave: Epistemologia; Inferencias Logicas; Representacao; Semiotica. Abstract: Where it is pertinent to the History of Logic, we could discern two types of logicians, namely: those that accept psychological principles to the reasoning and those that not accept such principles. Charles S. Peirce belonged to the second group and, about such matter, he had a certain position which he never changed his opinion, although this have only be consolidated in his maturity when he conceived his Classification of Sciences. In this article, we will not deal with such mature Peirce whose philosophical concepts are already consolidated. Our research will approach the roots of his philosophy mainly as to his concept of inferential process. Although it could seem a characteristic theme of logic, the question that we are proposing is to consider as the human mind equipped with this inferential process deals with the acquisition of knowledge without take psychological aspects into consideration. Thus, starting from the assumption of the unpsychological aspect attributed to the logic, we will intend to establish the principles that ground the existence of a substrate of the same nature between the cognizant and the cognizable, in a such way the acquired product, that is, the knowledge established in the form of a thought not be reduced to a human mental creation.

2 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: Accepting the consonance of Peircean semiotics with the arguments in the letter to Symonds, it is possible to deduce from Charles's writings other general passages that, if specifically applied, could serve as critiques of homophobia and help to contextualize the sentiments in theletter.
Abstract: ions but to persons; not to persons we do not know, nor to numbers of people, but to our own dear ones, our family and neighbors. 'Our neighbor,' we remember, is one whom we live near, not locally perhaps but in life and feeling. . . . Growth comes only from love, from I will not say self-sacrifice, but from the ardent impulse to fulfill another's highest impulse."' This element of self-control is where both Peirce brothers and Symonds himself stopped short of a full-fledged celebration of homosexual love. It was valuable only insofar as it remained "high minded," that is, where a relationship of spiritual respect existed between the parties. As Symonds wrote in his discussion of Whitman's "Calamus" poems from Leaves of Grass, "what he calls the 'adhesiveness' of comradeship is meant to have no interblending with the `amativeness' of sexual love. . . . Whitman possesses a specially keen sense of the fine restraint and continence, the cleanliness and chastity, that are inseparable from the perfectly virile and physically complete nature of healthy manhood." In the late nineteenth century, even its defenders could only conceive of--or dare articulate--a moral homosexuality governed by control similar to the Victorian ideal of heterosexual love.' 1-0 CP 6:25-26, par. 32, from "The Minute Logic" (ca. 1902). In The Collected Papers the editors divide Peirce's writings by topic, fragmenting otherwise complete works like "The Minute Logic." 11 CP 7:317, par. 532 (undated manuscript). 12 CP 6:192, pars. 289-90, from "Evolutionary Love" (ca. 1893). This essay is included in almost any published collection of Peirce's writings; see Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel, eds., The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, 2 vols. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992), 1:352-72. 13 "John Addington Symonds, A Study in Modern Ethics (1891), reprinted in Sexual Inversion (New York: Medical Press of New York, 1964), 185. This content downloaded from 207.46.13.57 on Sat, 10 Sep 2016 05:23:27 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms The Peirce Brothers 157 Accepting the consonance of Peircean semiotics with the arguments in the letter to Symonds, it is possible to deduce from Charles's writings other general passages that, if specifically applied, could serve as critiques of homophobia and help to contextualize the sentiments in the letter. For instance, accepting that attraction to the same as well as to the opposite sex is natural, he wrote: To presume to say that a physiological operation, such as is reasoning, is good or bad, is a pre-scientific conception for which there is no warrant. It belongs to the theological era of thought about nature, during the reign of which men drag the images of the saints into the street, blackguard them and threaten them if they do not cause rain to fall. Nowadays, such conduct is deemed childish. Men no longer become angry with the attraction of gravitation; and it is equally absurd to praise or blame any natural operation of man's psycho-physical organism.14 Those who simply assert that heterosexuality is normal and refuse even to discuss the matter can be criticized by means of Peircean logic. Charles wrote that "'it is evident' is a phrase which only means 'we do not know how to prove." The proposition that "we can immediately perceive only what is present" he considered "a vulgar prejudice," and "an opinion which can only defend itself by such a pretty sounding phrase is sure to be wrong."' If we can only perceive heterosexuality as the norm in the nineteenth century, one might conclude, Charles reminds us that it is not reasonable to argue that "whatever is, is right." Notably, the words "vulgar prejudice" also appear in James's letter to Symonds: "There is an error in the view that feminine love is that which is directed to a man and masculine love that which is directed to a woman. That doctrine involves a begging of the whole question. It is a fatal concession to vulgar prejudice and, indeed, I may say, to all the natural evolution of our race." Men can love other men, and women other women. Charles also denied this general distinction in the first characteristic he presented of pragmaticist or "critical common-sensist thought": "The Critical Commonsensist holds that all the veritably indubitable beliefs are vague."1-0 Charles also posed the interesting question that if a given behavior (and here one might choose to understand homosexuality) were so obviously wrong or unnatural, why did it excite such anger in its opponents? This was true "not only in questions of morals, but even in mere matters of manners, such as corporal pudor [physical modesty]." He continued: No matter how strong and well-rooted in habit any rational conviction of ours may be, we no sooner find that another equally well-informed 14 CP2:85, par. 155, from "The Minute Logic." 15 CP 1:16, par. 38, from an unpublished review of F. K. Abbott's translation of Immanuel Kant's Introduction to Logic (undated manuscript). 16 CP 5:355, par. 505, from "Pragmatism" (ca. 1905). This content downloaded from 207.46.13.57 on Sat, 10 Sep 2016 05:23:27 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

2 citations