scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question

Showing papers on "Skeptical theism published in 2018"


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, it was shown that good-god theism is not rendered unreasonable by the problem of evil in the same way that evil-god belief in good is rendered unreasonable.
Abstract: This article is a response to Stephen Law's article ‘The evil-god challenge’. In his article, Law argues that if belief in evil-god is unreasonable, then belief in good-god is unreasonable; that the antecedent is true; and hence so is the consequent. In this article, I show that Law's affirmation of the antecedent is predicated on the problem of good (i.e. the problem of whether an all-evil, all-powerful, and all-knowing God would allow there to be as much good in the world as there is), and argue that the problem of good fails. Thus, the antecedent is unmotivated, which renders the consequent unmotivated. Law's challenge for good-god theists is to show that good-god theism is not rendered unreasonable by the problem of evil in the same way that evil-god theism is rendered unreasonable by the problem of good. Insofar as the problem of good does not render belief in evil-god unreasonable, Law's challenge has been answered: since it is not unreasonable to believe in evil-god (at least for the reasons that Law gives) it is not unreasonable to believe in good-god. Finally, I show that – my criticism aside – the evil-god challenge turns out to be more complicated and controversial than it initially appears, for it relies on the (previously unacknowledged) contentious assumption that sceptical theism is false.

14 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: A decision-theoretic model for practical reasoning is described which is deontological so as to appeal to theists, but is designed not to presuppose any substantive moral commitments, and to accommodate normative and non-normative uncertainty.
Abstract: This article sets out a formal procedure for determining the probability that God would do a specified action, using our moral knowledge and understanding God as a perfect being. To motivate developing the procedure I show how natural theology – design arguments, the problems of evil and divine hiddenness, and the treatment of miracles and religious experiences as evidence for claims about God – routinely appeals to judgments involving these probabilities. To set out the procedure, I describe a decision-theoretic model for practical reasoning which is deontological so as to appeal to theists, but is designed not to presuppose any substantive moral commitments, and to accommodate normative and non-normative uncertainty. Then I explain how judgments about what we probably ought to do can be transformed into judgments about what God would probably do. Then I show the usefulness of the procedure by describing how it can help structure discussions in natural theology and a-theology, and how it offers an attractive alternative to ‘skeptical theism’.

6 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In fact, Dougherty is committed to the incompatibility of skeptical theism and commonsense epistemology, since, by his definitions of them, they entail contradictory propositions as mentioned in this paper.
Abstract: 1See his “Epistemological Considerations,” “Further Epistemological Considerations,” and “Phenomenal Conservatism.” 2More exactly, he claims that there is at least a superficial tension between commonsense epistemology and skeptical theism, and he issues a challenge to skeptical theists to remedy this tension. I use my terminology for the sake of simplicity. A referee suggests that this makes it appear that I am addressing a straw man. However, as I show below, Dougherty is, in fact, committed to the incompatibility of skeptical theism and commonsense epistemology, since, by his definitions of them, they entail contradictory propositions (i.e., (7) and (8)). See n. 5 for more on this.

5 citations



Journal ArticleDOI
Daniel Linford1
01 Mar 2018-Sophia
TL;DR: In this article, the evidential problem of good vs. evil is resolved by assuming the moral facts are identical to God's commands or favorings, but not what God favors for Herself to do.
Abstract: Gerald Harrison has recently argued the evidential problem of evil can be resolved if we assume the moral facts are identical to God’s commands or favorings. On a theistic metaethics, the moral facts are identical to what God commands or favors. Our moral intuitions reflect what God commands or favors for us to do, but not what God favors for Herself to do. Thus, on Harrison’s view, while we can know the moral facts as they pertain to humans, we cannot know the moral facts as they pertain to God. Therefore, Harrison argues, the evidential problem of evil inappropriately assumes God to be intuitively moral, when we have no reason to suppose a perfectly good being would match the expectations provided by our moral intuitions. Harrison calls his view a new form of skeptical theism. In response, I show Harrison’s attempt to dissolve the problem of evil exacerbates well-known skeptical consequences of skeptical theism. Harrison’s new skeptical theism leaves us with problems motivating a substantive religious life, the inability to provide a variety of theological explanations, and, despite Harrison’s comments to the contrary, worsens problems having to do with the possibility of divine deception.

1 citations


Journal Article
TL;DR: According to the Global Skepticism Objection, Skeptical Theism has as a consequence that we should not be surprised if we are radically deceived by God as mentioned in this paper, and Law presents an amusing analogy abou...
Abstract: According to the Global Skepticism Objection, Skeptical Theism has as a consequence that we should not be surprised if we are radically deceived by God. Stephen Law presents an amusing analogy abou ...