scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question
Topic

Sure-thing principle

About: Sure-thing principle is a research topic. Over the lifetime, 96 publications have been published within this topic receiving 16301 citations.


Papers
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI
Daniel Ellsberg1
TL;DR: The notion of "degrees of belief" was introduced by Knight as mentioned in this paper, who argued that people tend to behave "as though" they assigned numerical probabilities to events, or degrees of belief to the events impinging on their actions.
Abstract: Are there uncertainties that are not risks? There has always been a good deal of skepticism about the behavioral significance of Frank Knight's distinction between “measurable uncertainty” or “risk”, which may be represented by numerical probabilities, and “unmeasurable uncertainty” which cannot. Knight maintained that the latter “uncertainty” prevailed – and hence that numerical probabilities were inapplicable – in situations when the decision-maker was ignorant of the statistical frequencies of events relevant to his decision; or when a priori calculations were impossible; or when the relevant events were in some sense unique; or when an important, once-and-for-all decision was concerned. Yet the feeling has persisted that, even in these situations, people tend to behave “as though” they assigned numerical probabilities, or “degrees of belief,” to the events impinging on their actions. However, it is hard either to confirm or to deny such a proposition in the absence of precisely-defined procedures for measuring these alleged “degrees of belief.” What might it mean operationally, in terms of refutable predictions about observable phenomena, to say that someone behaves “as if” he assigned quantitative likelihoods to events: or to say that he does not? An intuitive answer may emerge if we consider an example proposed by Shackle, who takes an extreme form of the Knightian position that statistical information on frequencies within a large, repetitive class of events is strictly irrelevant to a decision whose outcome depends on a single trial.

7,005 citations

Book ChapterDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors trace the violations of the rational theory of choice to the rules that govern the framing of decision and to the psychological principles of evaluation embodied in prospect theory, and argue that these rules are normatively essential but descriptively invalid.
Abstract: Alternative descriptions of a decision problem often give rise to different preferences, contrary to the principle of invariance that underlines the rational theory of choice. Violations of this theory are traced to the rules that govern the framing of decision and to the psychological principles of evaluation embodied in prospect theory. Invariance and dominance are obeyed when their application is transparent and often violated in other situations. Because these rules are normatively essential but descriptively invalid, no theory of choice can be both normatively adequate and descriptively accurate.

4,243 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the Ellsberg paradox was used to reject one of Savage's main axioms -the Sure Thing Principle -and develop a more general theory, in which the probability measure need not be additive.

814 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: When thinking under uncertainty, people often do not consider appropriately each of the relevant branches of a decision tree, as required by consequentialism, and sometimes violate Savage's sure-thing principle.

635 citations

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors suggest that people are often reluctant to think through the implications of each outcome and, as a result, may violate the sure-thing principle of decision under uncertainty.
Abstract: One of the basic axioms of the rational theory of decision under uncertainty is Savage's (1954) sure-thing principle (STP) It states that if prospect x is preferred to y knowing that Event A occurred, and if x is preferred to y knowing that A did not occur, then x should be preferred to y even when it is not known whether A occurred We present examples in which the decision maker has good reasons for accepting x if A occurs, and different reasons for accepting x if A does not occur Not knowing whether or not A occurs, however, the decision maker may lack a clear reason for accepting x and may opt for another option We suggest that, in the presence of uncertainty, people are often reluctant to think through the implications of each outcome and, as a result, may violate STP This interpretation is supported by the observation that STP is satisfied when people are made aware of their preferences given each outcome

596 citations


Network Information
Related Topics (5)
Normative
15.2K papers, 399.1K citations
72% related
Public good
19K papers, 605.3K citations
70% related
Rationality
20.4K papers, 617.7K citations
70% related
Game theory
28.4K papers, 780.9K citations
70% related
Empirical research
51.3K papers, 1.9M citations
69% related
Performance
Metrics
No. of papers in the topic in previous years
YearPapers
20211
20203
20191
20184
20174
20164