scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question

Showing papers by "Nicola Guarino published in 2002"


Book ChapterDOI
01 Oct 2002
TL;DR: This paper introduces the DOLCE upper level ontology, the first module of a Foundational Ontologies Library being developed within the WonderWeb project, and suggests that such analysis could hopefully lead to an ?
Abstract: In this paper we introduce the DOLCE upper level ontology, the first module of a Foundational Ontologies Library being developed within the WonderWeb project. DOLCE is presented here in an intuitive way; the reader should refer to the project deliverable for a detailed axiomatization. A comparison with WordNet's top-level taxonomy of nouns is also provided, which shows how DOLCE, used in addition to the OntoClean methodology, helps isolating and understanding some major WordNet?s semantic limitations. We suggest that such analysis could hopefully lead to an ?ontologically sweetened? WordNet, meant to be conceptually more rigorous, cognitively transparent, and efficiently exploitable in several applications.

1,100 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: Explosing common misuses of the subsumption relationship and the formal basis for why they are wrong and how to stop them.
Abstract: Explosing common misuses of the subsumption relationship and the formal basis for why they are wrong.

825 citations


01 Jan 2002
TL;DR: The endurants/perdurants distinction introduced in the previous section provides evidence for the general necessity of having two kinds of parthood, and a basic primitive relation is an immediate relation that spans multiple application domains.
Abstract: entities The main characteristic of abstract entities is that they do not have spatial nor temporal qualities, and they are not qualities themselves. The only class of abstract entities we consider in the present version of DOLCE is that of quality regions (or simply regions). Quality spaces are special kinds of quality regions, being mereological sums of all the regions related to a certain quality type. The other examples of abstract entities reported in Figure 2 (sets and facts) are only indicative. 2.3 Basic functions and relations According to the general methodology introduced in [Gangemi et al. 2001], before discussing the DOLCE backbone properties, we have first to introduce a set of basic primitive relations, suitable to characterize our ontological commitments as neutrally as possible. We believe that these relations should be, as much as possible, • general enough to be applied to multiple domains; • such that they do not rest on questionable ontological assumptions about the ontological nature of their arguments; • sufficiently intuitive and well studied in the philosophical literature; • hold as soon as their relata are given, without mediating additional entities. In the past, we adopted the term formal relation (as opposite to material relation) for a relation that can be applied to all possible domains. Recently, however, [Degen et al. 2001] proposed a different notion of formal relation: “A relation is formal if it holds as soon as its relata are given. Formal relations are called equivalently immediate relations, since they hold of their relata without mediating additional individuals”. The notion of basic primitive relation proposed above combines together the two notions. Roughly, a basic primitive relation is an immediate relation that spans multiple application domains. The axioms constraining the arguments of primitive relations and functions are reported in Table 3, and summarized in Figure 4. 1 The notion of ‘immediate relation’ seems to be equivalent to what Johansson called ground relation [Johansson 1989]. According to Johansson, a ground relation “is derivable from its relata”. We understand that the very existence of the arguments is sufficient to conclude whether the relation holds or not. This notion seems also equivalent to that of “internal relation”. IST Project 2001-33052 WonderWeb: Ontology Infrastructure for the Semantic Web 14 Parthood: “x is part of y” P(x, y) → (AB(x) ∨ PD(x)) ∧ (AB(y) ∨ PD(y)) Temporary Parthood: “x is part of y during t” P(x, y, t) → (ED(x) ∧ ED(y) ∧ T(t)) Constitution: “x constitutes y during t” K(x, y, t) → ((ED(x) ∨ PD(x)) ∧ (ED(y) ∨ PD(y)) ∧ T(t)) Participation: “x participates in y during t” PC(x, y, t) → (ED(x) ∧ PD(y) ∧ T(t)) Quality: “x is a quality of y” qt(x, y) → (Q(x) ∧ (Q(y) ∨ ED(y) ∨ PD(y))) Quale: “x is the quale of y (during t)” ql(x, y) → (TR(x) ∧ TQ(y)) ql(x, y, t) → ((PR(x) ∨ AR(x)) ∧ (PQ(y) ∨ AQ(y)) ∧ T(t)) Table 3. Basic axioms on argument restrictions of primitives. Parthood and Temporary Parthood The endurants/perdurants distinction introduced in the previous section provides evidence for the general necessity of having two kinds of parthood relations: a-temporal and time-indexed parthood. The latter will hold for endurants, since for them it is necessary to know when a specific parthood relationship holds. Consider for instance the classical example of Tibbles the cat [Simons 1987]: Tail is part of Tibbles before the cut but not after it. Formally, we can write P(Tail, Tibbles, before(cut)) and ¬P(Tail, Tibbles, after(cut)). Atemporal parthood, on the other hand, will be used for entities which do not properly change in time (occurrences and abstracts). In the present version, parthood will not be defined for qualities. With respect to time-indexed parthood, two useful notions can be defined. We shall say that an endurant is mereologically constant iff all its parts remains the same during its life, and mereologically invariant iff they remain the same across all possible worlds. For example, we usually take ordinary material objects as mereologically variable, because during their life they can lose or gain parts. On the other hand, amounts of matter are taken as mereologically invariant (all their parts are essential parts). Dependence and Spatial Dependence There are basically two approaches to characterizing the notion of ontological dependence: • non-modal accounts (cf. [Fine and Smith 1983] and [Simons 1987] , pp. 310-318) • modal accounts (cf. [Simons 1987]). Non-modal approaches treat the dependence relation as a quasi-mereological primitive whose formal properties are characterized by axioms. However, as Simons has justly observed, such axiomatizations cannot rule out non-intended interpretations that are purely topological in nature. The only way to save them is actually to link them with modal accounts. In a modal approach, dependence of an entity x on an entity y might be defined as follows: x depends on y iff, necessarily, y is present whenever x is present. Such a definition seems to be in harmony both with commonsense intuition as well as philosophical tradition (Aristotle, Husserl), despite the fact that there are some cases where, as Kit Fine has shown, this characterization is vacuous. Indeed, according to the definition, everything is trivially dependent on necessarily existing or always present objects. However, Simons has shown that it is possible to exclude such vacuous examples and while this move might be philosophically dubious, it makes perfect sense in an engineering approach to ontologies of everyday IST Project 2001-33052 WonderWeb: Ontology Infrastructure for the Semantic Web 15 contingent objects. Our concept of dependence involves the notion of presence in time as well as modality. We mainly use two variants of dependence, adapted from [Thomasson 1999]: specific and generic constant dependence. The former is defined both for particulars and properties, while the latter only for properties. A particular x is specifically constantly dependent on another particular y iff, at any time t, x can't be present at t unless y is also present at t. For example, a person might be specifically constantly dependent on its brain. This notion is naturally extended to properties by defining that a property φ is specifically constantly dependent on a property ψ iff every φer is specifically constantly dependent on a ψ . A property φ is generically constantly dependent on a property ψ iff, for any instance x of φ, at any time t, x can't be present at t, unless a certain instance y of ψ is also present at t. For example, a person might be generically constantly dependent on having a heart. We define spatial dependence as a particular kind of dependence which is grounded not only in time (presence), but also in space. The definitions are as above with the further requirement that y has to be spatially co-localised with x in addition of being co-present. This notion is defined both for endurants and perdurants. Constitution Constitution has been extensively discussed in the philosophical literature: • Doepke (cit. in [Simons 1987] p.238) “x constitutes y at time t iff x could be a substratum of y’s destruction.” • Simons (cit. in [Simons 1987] p.239) “When x constitutes y, there are certain properties of x which are accidental to x, but essential to y. (...) Where the essential properties concern the type and disposition of parts, this is often a case of composition, but in other cases, such as that of body/person, it is not.” Constitution is not Identity – Consider the following classical example. I buy a portion of clay (LUMPL) at 9am. At 2pm I made a statue (GOLIATH) out of LUMPL and I put GOLIATH on a table. At 3pm I replace the left hand of GOLIATH with a new one and I throw the old hand in the dustbin. There are three reasons to support the claim that LUMPL is not GOLIATH: (i) Difference in histories LUMPL is present a 9am, but GOLIATH is not [Thomson 1998] (ii) Difference in persistence conditions At 3pm GOLIATH is wholly present on the table, but LUMPL is not wholly present on the table (a statue can undergo replacements of certain parts, but not an amount (portion) of matter, i.e. all parts of LUMPL are essential but not all parts of GOLIATH are essential [Thomson 1998]. LUMPL can survive a change of shape, GOLIATH not. (iii) Difference in essential relational properties It is metaphysically possible for LUMPL, but not for GOLIATH, to exist in the absence of an artworld or an artist or anybody's intentions [Baker 2000]. Participation The usual intuition about participation is that there are endurants “involved” in an occurrence. Linguistics has extensively investigated the relation between occurrences and their participants in order to classify verbs and verbal expressions. Fillmore's Case Grammar [Fillmore 1984] and its developments (Construction Grammar, FrameNet) is one of the best attempts at building a systematic model of language-oriented participants. On the other hand, the first systematic investigation goes back at least to Aristotle, that defined four “causes” (aitiai), expressing the initiator, the destination, the instrument, and the substrate or host of an event. Sowa further specified subsets of aitiai on the basis of properties borrowed from linguistics (cfr. [Sowa 1999]). In an ontology based on a strict distinction between endurants and perdurants, participation cannot be simply parthood; the participating endurants are not parts of the occurrences: only occurrences can be parts of other occurrences. Moreover, the primitive participation we IST Project 2001-33052 WonderWeb: Ontology Infrastructure for the Semantic Web 16 introduce is time-indexed, in order to account for the varieties of participation in time (temporary participation, constant participation). Quality inherence and quality value Finally, three primitive relations are introduced in order to account for qualities: a generalized

104 citations


Posted Content
TL;DR: In this article, the authors propose a method to solve the problem of homonymity of homophily in the context of homomorphic data, and no abstracts are available.
Abstract: No abstract available.

99 citations


Book ChapterDOI
01 Jan 2002
TL;DR: In this paper, the ontological nature of a taxonomy's arguments has been investigated in order to tell whether a single is-a link is ontologically well-founded, based on the philosophical notions of identity, unity, and essence.
Abstract: The intuitive simplicity of the so-called is-a (or subsumption) relationship has led to widespread ontological misuse. Where previous work has focused largely on the semantics of the relationship itself, we concentrate here on the ontological nature of its arguments, in order to tell whether a single is-a link is ontologically well-founded. For this purpose, we introduce some techniques based on the philosophical notions of identity, unity, and essence, which have been adapted to the needs of taxonomy design. We demonstrate the effectiveness of these techniques by taking real examples of poorly structured taxonomies and revealing cases of invalid generalization.

96 citations


01 Jan 2002
TL;DR: The result is a “cleaned-up” WordNet, which is meant to be conceptually more rigorous, cognitively transparent, and efficiently exploitable in several applications.
Abstract: In this paper we propose an analysis and a rearrangement of WordNet's top-level taxonomy of nouns. We briefly review WordNet and identify its main semantic limitations, in the light of the ontology evaluation principles lying at the core of the OntoClean methodology. Then we briefly present a first version of the OntoClean Top (OCT) ontology, and show how WordNet can be aligned with it. The result is a “cleaned-up” WordNet, which is meant to be conceptually more rigorous, cognitively transparent, and efficiently exploitable in several applications.

81 citations


Book ChapterDOI
07 Oct 2002
TL;DR: In the last decade, ontologies have become a hot issue in the conceptual modeling community, which is chiefly due to the emergence of new application areas such as Electronic Commerce and the Semantic Web.
Abstract: In the last decade, ontologies have become a hot issue in the conceptual modeling community, which is chiefly due to the emergence of new application areas such as Electronic Commerce and the Semantic Web. The implementation of large-scale information systems, as well as their semantic interoperability, seem to be only tractable on the basis of ontologies as abtract domain models.

42 citations