scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessJournal Article

Adam Smith’s Reconstruction of Practical Reason

María Alejandra Carrasco
- 01 Feb 2004 - 
- Vol. 58, Iss: 1, pp 81-116
TLDR
In the last part of the Theory of Moral Sentiments, Adam Smith put his theory in a class with those of his contemporaries Francis Hutcheson and David Hume, namely, the systems that make sentiments the principle of approbation as mentioned in this paper.
Abstract
IN THE LAST PART of the Theory of Moral Sentiments, (1) Adam Smith puts his theory in a class with those of his contemporaries Francis Hutcheson and David Hume, namely, the systems that make sentiments the principle of approbation. (2) Despite recognizing important differences with both of them, he thinks that since he has placed the origin of moral sentiments in sympathy, and in particular the fact that we are able to enter into the motives of the agent and get pleasure from finding them appropriate (proportionate) to their cause, sentiments are the foundation of his theory of morals. Many of Smith's commentators, in fact almost all of the most important studies over the last few years, reaffirm the author's self-description. (3) However, my aim in this paper is to challenge this view by showing that Smith's system can also be plausibly seen as a theory of practical reasoning, and in some important aspects very similar to Aristotelian ethics. (4) Surprisingly few scholars have seen this parallel. Laurence Berns, Samuel Fleischacker, Charles Griswold, and Gloria Vivenza are the latest exceptions, (5) identifying several points of coincidence between Adam Smith and Aristotle's ethics. None of them, however, has tied all these similarities under a unified interpretation, such as the one I propose here: The basic analogy between these theories, and the source of those particular coincidences, is the operation (implicit in TMS) of practical reason. Moreover, and besides the common elements with Aristotle's ethics, Smith's reconstruction of practical reason simultaneously announces some of the main features of modern accounts of ethics, such as impartiality and universality as preconditions of moral judgment. The integration of these ancient and modern elements in a single coherent theory allows Smith's TMS to overcome the insufficiencies and paradoxes of both these traditions, (6) and it constitutes one of the most interesting and challenging proposals of modern ethics. The first obvious question to be raised, therefore, is why Smith and his commentators underestimate the role played by reason in this system. Although this will not be my topic, I would like to suggest that the problem is mainly a "wrong labeling" due, it seems, to historical and contextual reasons. In Smith's time the concept of practical reason was in complete disuse until Kant rehabilitated it, in a totally different form, at the end of the century. The classical Aristotelian concept of practical reason, though, had to wait until the twentieth century for its vindication. (7) Moreover, one of Smith's main motivations for articulating his theory, just like Hutcheson and Hume, was to refute Hobbes's and Mandeville's egoistic ethics. Therefore, discarding medieval theological systems and the implausible (for them) rationalistic theories of some of their modern predecessors (the Cambridge Platonists), sentiments were the natural alternative for these three philosophers, especially since they aimed to found morality on a naturalistic basis, rejecting metaphysical explanations. Hutcheson and Hume accomplished their goal, proposing two different sentimentalist accounts of ethics. Smith, however, mainly through the introduction of the supposed impartial spectator, (8) ended up constructing a system of practical reason. This paper will start by showing why the principle of approbation in TMS is neither theoretical reason nor sentiments, or, in other words, why we should reject both the rationalistic and the sentimentalist interpretation of Smith's ethics. In the second and third sections I will give a brief account of the theoretical framework of my argument: the general structure of the human faculty of practical reason (section 2), and three of its Aristotelian features that I want to highlight (section 3). The main thrust of my argument comes in section 4, where I interpret TMS as a system of practical reason, identifying the topics which I believe give enough evidence to support my thesis. …

read more

Citations
More filters
Book

Adam Smith and the Character of Virtue

TL;DR: In this paper, the authors discuss the what and how of TMS VI and discuss the problem of commerce and corruption and the solution of moral philosophy, which is the basis of our work.
Journal ArticleDOI

Will the Real A. Smith Please Stand Up

TL;DR: The authors argue that Smith, far from being an advocate of a value-free or even value-averse conception of economic transactions, stood for a virtue-based and values-oriented model of business, and argue current management education and the pedagogy of business ethics should be changed, and certain strategic conclusions drawn for business practice.
Book ChapterDOI

Adam Smith as an eclectic Stoic

Journal ArticleDOI

Reading Adam Smith after Darwin: On the evolution of propensities, institutions, and sentiments

TL;DR: This paper calls attention to Smith's "Considerations Concerning the First Formation of Languages" in order to facilitate understanding Adam Smith from an evolutionary perspective and claims that in TMS there is a distinction between natural sentiments and moral sentiments.
Journal ArticleDOI

The Unreality Business - How Economics (and Management) Became Anti-philosophical

TL;DR: The authors argues that economics has become steadily more anti-philosophical and that there are three stages in the development of economic thought: Adam Smith intended economics to be a descriptive social science, rooted in an understanding of the moral and psychological processes of an individual's decision-making and its connection to society in general.