scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question

Showing papers in "Sophia in 2009"


Journal ArticleDOI
24 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors argue that naturalists have no proper basis to oppose the existence of supernatural entities and that naturalism is characterized as a position which involves a primary commitment to scientific methodology and any naturalistic ontological commitments must be compatible with this primary commitment.
Abstract: There is overwhelming agreement amongst naturalists that a naturalistic ontology should not allow for the possibility of supernatural entities. I argue, against this prevailing consensus, that naturalists have no proper basis to oppose the existence of supernatural entities. Naturalism is characterized, following Leiter and Rea, as a position which involves a primary commitment to scientific methodology and it is argued that any naturalistic ontological commitments must be compatible with this primary commitment. It is further argued that properly applied scientific method has warranted the acceptance of the existence of supernatural entities in the past and that it is plausible to think that it will do so again in the future. So naturalists should allow for the possibility of supernatural entities.

21 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
Monima Chadha1
03 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The Naiyayika theory of perception has been used in contemporary philosophy of mind as discussed by the authors, where the authors argue that some aspects of the Cartesian conception of mind continue to influence the work of contemporary theorists.
Abstract: In this paper I aim to situate the Naiyayika theory of perception in contemporary philosophy of mind. Following the ancients, I suggest we reconsider the taxonomy and the assumed interactions between kinds of perceptual content. This reclassification will lead us to reconsider some aspects of the Cartesian conception of mind that continue to influence the work of contemporary theorists. I focus attention on different accounts of sensory perception favoured by ancient Indian Naiyayika philosophers and Descartes as a starting point for reconsidering contemporary accounts of perceptual content.I show that Descartes' account of sensory perception provides the impetus for a causal-explanatory account of conceptual content in terms of its non-conceptual counterpart. Though contemporary philosophers claim to have cast off their Cartesian heritage, my discussion reveals that some of its tenets continue to influence the work of contemporary philosophers. I offer reasons for rejecting yet another Cartesian influence and recommend that we follow the Nyaya taxonomy of perceptual states.

16 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
30 Jun 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The presente trabajo no tiene por objetivo ni definir el arte, ni hacer una critica sobre los procesos llevados in el medio artistico; sin embargo, busca poner en vitro la discusion sobre la efectividad simbolica del arte.
Abstract: El presente trabajo no tiene por objetivo ni definir el arte, ni hacer una critica sobre los procesos llevados a cabo en el medio artistico; sin embargo, busca poner en el tapete la discusion sobre la efectividad simbolica del arte; como su caracter comunicacional puede ser utilizado por el poder y como, a traves de la historia, el arte ha colaborado con procesos de dominacion. En el texto no se intenta definir el arte, por el contrario, se menciona el pensamiento de Croce sobre lo que no deberia ser, con el fin de establecer la razon por la que ciertas concepciones han utilizado el arte como medio de propaganda politica. Posteriormente, se vincula al arte como simbolo, identificandolo como una construccion cargada de significados, inherentes a su epoca pero con vigencia en los imaginarios; al estar cargado de significados considero que el arte trata de hacer una revision somera sobre si mismo, con algunos hitos relevantes, con la aclaracion que esta sujeto a una historia del arte occidental.

15 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
15 Oct 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The authors argue that the notion of God as an immaterial personal creator with the omni-properties may reasonably be judged inadequate, at any rate from the perspective of a relationship ethics based on the Christian revelation that God is Love.
Abstract: Theistic religious believers should be concerned that the God they worship is not an idol. Conceptions of God thus need to be judged according to criteria of religious adequacy that are implicit in the ‘God-role’—that is, the way the concept of God properly functions in the conceptual economy and form of life of theistic believers. I argue that the conception of God as ‘omniGod’—an immaterial personal creator with the omni-properties—may reasonably be judged inadequate, at any rate from the perspective of a relationship ethics based on the Christian revelation that God is Love. I go on to suggest that a conception of God as the power of love within the natural universe might prove more adequate, with God’s role as creator understood in terms of final rather than efficient causation.

11 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
29 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this article, the authors explore the Rousseauian background to Kant's critique of metaphysics and philosophical theology, and demonstrate the importance of practical philosophy for Kant and the critical project generally.
Abstract: This paper explores the Rousseauian background to Kant’s critique of metaphysics and philosophical theology. The core idea is that the rejection of metaphysics and philosophical theology is part of a turn from theoretical to practical reason influential on European philosophy of religion, a turn we associate with Kant but that is prefigured by Rousseau. Rousseau is not, however, a thinker normally associated with the notion of metaphysical criticism, nor the notion of the primacy of practical reason. The paper draws out this dimension of Rousseau’s thinking and its importance for Kantian thought. It will proceed by discussing the Kant-Rousseau connection; demonstrate the importance of practical philosophy for Kant and the critical project generally; overview Kant’s critique of metaphysics; and turn to a consideration of Rousseau, particularly from the text Emile. Given the indisputable influence of Rousseau on Kant, the purpose of this paper is to explore the ways that Rousseau’s own rejection of philosophical theology might be suggestive to those interested in Kant and the way in which it throws new light on Kant’s philosophy of religion. As well as drawing out the Kant-Rousseau connection, it also, implicitly, defends the general orientation of these philosophers as one that is important, perhaps vital, to philosophy of religion.

8 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
Rebecca Hanrahan1
31 Oct 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The authors argue that such appeals to God can not provide us with a guide to possibility, for either God's powers are co-extensive with the possible or they are not, and if they are, these appeals either beg the question or court a version of Euthyphro's Dilemma.
Abstract: Some hold that if we can imagine God creating a world in which a particular proposition (p) is true, then we can conclude that p is possible. I argue that such appeals to God can’t provide us with a guide to possibility. For either God’s powers aren’t co-extensive with the possible or they are. And if they are, these appeals either beg the question or court a version of Euthyphro’s Dilemma. Some may argue that such appeals were only intended to prompt us to think broadly about the modal claim at issue. I argue instead that these appeals must be understood as more than mere prompts. For it is these appeals that would, if successful, render the conceivability principle viable.

6 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Aug 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors demonstrate that Veber's argument is simply the logical problem of evil applied to a possible world, and that it is susceptible to a Plantinga-style defense.
Abstract: In a previous issue of this journal Michael Veber argued that God could not answer certain prayers because doing so would be immoral. In this article I attempt to demonstrate that Veber’s argument is simply the logical problem of evil applied to a possible world. Because of this, his argument is susceptible to a Plantinga-style defense.

6 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
Nathan Eric Dickman1
18 Aug 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this article, a sketch aimed at adapting Tillich's theological system grounded in existential questioning to today by juxtaposing him with Levinas' philosophical ethics is presented, which is the starting point for this paper.
Abstract: With almost a century of historical distance between Heidegger’s retrieval of the question of being and contemporary concern about the Other, we have accrued invaluable experiences for critical leverage about what it is to ask one another questions. I offer a sketch aimed at adapting Tillich’s theological system grounded in existential questioning to today by juxtaposing him with Levinas’ philosophical ethics. Tillich and Levinas provide motive for reflection on the topic of questioning in particular. In the case of Tillich, questions constitute a crucial moment in the dialogue between our contemporary existential situation and religious symbols, or in what he called the ‘method of correlation.’ Furthermore, Tillich locates in the very structure of questioning the germ of our participation in our essential nature despite existential disruption. Beneath his more provocative and prophetic discourse on the absolute desolation and height of the Other, Levinas sees in questions a different kind of possibility. It is not our essential and existential selves, but oneself and the absolutely Other who come together in the question yet retain their infinite difference. Heidegger is the immediate predecessor from whom both Tillich and Levinas inherit a predilection for reflection on questioning. What is at stake is not merely the legacy of Heidegger’s construal of questioning, but, more importantly here, the fundamental sources Tillich and Levinas posit as the origin of our questioning.

6 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
Mark Maller1
21 Mar 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: This essay critically evaluating the theodicies of John Hick, Richard Swinburne and process theism regarding animal suffering and evils are found to be flawed and/or inadequate because they cannot explain the mass suffering and unnecessary deaths to animals throughout time.
Abstract: This essay critically evaluates the theodicies of John Hick, Richard Swinburne and process theism regarding animal suffering and evils. Their positions on animals are found to be flawed and/or inadequate because they cannot explain the mass suffering and unnecessary deaths to animals throughout time. I also offer a positive contribution. That is, God’s putative love for all humans and animals does not entail that he loves every single human and animal. It is very possible that God treats humans and animals similarly in regard to evils. This theory partly explains human tragedies such as the Holocaust and much unnecessary animal and human suffering.

6 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
03 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors compare two very different deployments of love in ethics: Swami Vivekananda's concept of ethical love ties into the project of constructing an alternative masculinity for a colonized people; while feminist care ethics uses love to escape the perceived masculinity of traditional ethical theory.
Abstract: In this paper I compare two very different deployments of love in ethics. Swami Vivekananda's concept of ethical love ties into the project of constructing an alternative masculinity for a colonized people; while feminist care ethics uses love to escape the perceived masculinity of traditional ethical theory. Using Kenneth Goodpaster's distinction between ‘framework questions’ and ‘application questions,’ I try to show that love in Practical Vedanta addresses the former while feminist care ethics concerns itself with the latter. Even though this difference, I suggest, could be a function of their varying historical-political contexts, the two issues need to be taken together for a more complete understanding of the ethical subject.

6 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
28 Nov 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this article, the authors explore the structure of what Jean Wahl calls "transascendance", a rising to the heights of Christian theology and philosophy, both ancient and modern Contemplation, in ancient philosophy, is transformed in Christian theology.
Abstract: This essay seeks to explore contemplation as it features in Christian theology and philosophy, both ancient and modern Contemplation, in ancient philosophy, is transformed in Christian theology; nonetheless, it has the structure of what Jean Wahl calls ‘transascendance’, a rising to the heights Although contemplation remains as a theme in modern Christian theology, it drops out in modern philosophy: that is, post-Renaissance philosophy And yet it returns, both in analytic and continental philosophy, in the twentieth century It returns, however, in the mode of ‘transdescendance’: by way of conditions of possibility, and fundamental orientations

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: A philosophical theory of religion should be extensionally accurate, neutral, phenomenological, and non-circular as mentioned in this paper, and none of the popular theories of religion meet these criteria.
Abstract: A philosophical theory of religion ought to meet four criteria: it should be extensionally accurate, neutral, phenomenological, and non-circular. I argue that none of the popular theories of religion meet all these criteria, and that, in particular, the extensional accuracy criterion and the non-circularity criterion can’t be met without sacrificing extensional accuracy. I conclude that, therefore, religions do not form a kind, and so, there is no such thing as religion.

Journal ArticleDOI
30 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors highlight a second manner in which miracles and the problem of evil relate, and they give reason as to why what is considered to be miraculous may be dependent upon a particular response to the natural evil.
Abstract: Miracles and the problem of evil are two prominent areas of research within philosophy of religion. On occasion these areas converge, with God’s goodness being brought into question by the claim that either there is a lack of miracles, or there are immoral miracles. In this paper I shall highlight a second manner in which miracles and the problem of evil relate. Namely, I shall give reason as to why what is considered to be miraculous may be dependent upon a particular response to the problem of natural evil. To establish this claim, I shall focus upon Aquinas’s definition of a miracle and a particular free-will defence, the Luciferous defence.

Journal ArticleDOI
02 Dec 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The authors argue that Winch's relationship to relativism is widely misinterpreted in that, despite his pluralistic understanding of rationality, Winch does allow for universal features of culture in virtue of which cross-cultural understanding and even critique is possible.
Abstract: Many point to Peter Winch’s discussion of rationality, relativism, and religion as a paradigmatic example of cultural relativism. In this paper, I argue that Winch’s relationship to relativism is widely misinterpreted in that, despite his pluralistic understanding of rationality, Winch does allow for universal features of culture in virtue of which cross-cultural understanding and even critique is possible. Nevertheless, I also argue that given the kind of cultural universals that Winch produces, he fails to avoid relativism. This is because in order to provide the standards without which relativism ensues, one requires a certain kind of criteria of rationality, namely, what I here call substantive universals, a kind of criteria which Winch rejects.

Journal ArticleDOI
30 Jun 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: Swinburne relies on principle P in The Existence of God to argue that God is simple and thus likely to exist as mentioned in this paper, but does not support P in particular, his arguments from mathematical simplicity and scientists' preferences both fail.
Abstract: Swinburne relies on principle P in The Existence of God to argue that God is simple and thus likely to exist In this paper, I argue that Swinburne does not support P In particular, his arguments from mathematical simplicity and scientists’ preferences both fail Given the central role P plays in Swinburne’s overall argument in The Existence of God, I conclude that Swinburne should further support P if his argument that God likely exists is to be persuasive

Journal ArticleDOI
07 Nov 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The anthropic argument as discussed by the authors is related to, but distinct from, the traditional argument from good to evil, and it forces us to consider the creation question: why did God not create other gods rather than humans?
Abstract: If God is morally perfect then He must perform the morally best actions, but creating humans is not the morally best action. If this line of reasoning can be maintained then the mere fact that humans exist contradicts the claim that God exists. This is the ‘anthropic argument’. The anthropic argument, is related to, but distinct from, the traditional argument from evil. The anthropic argument forces us to consider the ‘creation question’: why did God not create other gods rather than humans? That is, if God is omniscient, omnipotent, and morally perfect then why didn’t He create a world populated exclusively by beings that are perfect in the same way that He is—ontological equivalents— rather than choosing to create humans with finite natures and all the suffering that this entails?

Journal ArticleDOI
11 Aug 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The authors make a connection between the cosmic jackpot of life in the universe and the uniquely human activity that takes place in the political realm and conclude that action is nothing less than the activity of world-making.
Abstract: Arendt’s theoretical influence is generally traced to Heidegger and experientially to the traumatic events that occurred in Europe during the Second World War. Here, we suggest that Arendt’s conception of politics may be usefully enriched via a proto-anthropic principle found in Augustine and adopted by Arendt throughout her writings. By appealing to this anthropic principle; that without a spectator there could be no world; a profound connection is made between the ‘cosmic jackpot’ of life in the universe and the uniquely human activity that takes place in the political realm. By making this connection we suggest that solutions present themselves to a central puzzle arising in Arendt’s thought: namely, what it is that people actually do in the political realm. The first solution directly addresses the issue of content: what people talk about in Arendt’s public space. The second addresses the importance of ‘maintaining’ a space of appearances. The third considers the effect of participating in and observing the public domain. Consequently, we conclude that, for Arendt, action is nothing less than the activity of ‘world-making.’

Journal ArticleDOI
29 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: A central theme in the Christian contemplative tradition is that knowing God is much more like "unknowing" than it is like possessing rationally acceptable beliefs as discussed by the authors, and this has implications for his project of demonstrating the rational acceptability of Christian faith for the 21st century.
Abstract: A central theme in the Christian contemplative tradition is that knowing God is much more like ‘unknowing’ than it is like possessing rationally acceptable beliefs. Knowledge of God is expressed, in this tradition, in metaphors of woundedness, darkness, silence, suffering, and desire. Philosophers of religion, on the other hand, tend to explore the possibilities of knowing God in terms of rational acceptability, epistemic rights, cognitive responsibility, and propositional belief. These languages seem to point to very different accounts of how it is that we come to know God, and a very different range of critical concepts by which the truth of such knowledge can be assessed. In this paper, I begin to explore what might be at stake in these different languages of knowing God, drawing particularly on Alvin Plantinga’s epistemology of Christian belief. I will argue that his is a distorted account of the epistemology of Christian belief, and that this has implications for his project of demonstrating the rational acceptability of Christian faith for the 21st century.


Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: Eddy and Knight as mentioned in this paper published a new edition of Paley's Natural Theology, which is the standard scholarly edition of what is a historically, theologically, and philosophically important work.
Abstract: Matthew D. Eddy and David Knight’s new edition of William Paley’s Natural Theology deserves to become the standard scholarly edition of what is a historically, theologically, and philosophically important work, despite a certain neglect of philosophical issues on the part of the editors.


Journal ArticleDOI
30 Dec 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: A prioridad de la acumulación de la información se presta a la destruccion de la subjetivivivdad, e.g., la educación construye sujetos...cuando no los destruye as discussed by the authors.
Abstract: La educacion construye sujetos...cuando no los destruye. La prioridad de la acumulacion de la informacion se presta a la destruccion de la subjetivivdad

Journal ArticleDOI
17 Apr 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: The study of religion by social anthropologists, as distinct from the classical philosophical approach of the Greeks and their medieval heirs, began in the late 19th century with Edward Tyler's Primitive Culture (1871) as discussed by the authors.
Abstract: The study of religion by social anthropologists, as distinct from the classical philosophical approach of the Greeks and their medieval heirs, began in the late 19th century with Edward Tyler’s Primitive Culture (1871). Tyler’s approach was completely a priori in style in that it did not rest on systematic field work or empirical observation. The same approach characterized James Frazer’s famous book, The Golden Bough (1891). Baldwin Spencer, the founding father of Australian anthropology, was persuaded by Frazer to see the sophisticated religious beliefs and rites of the Aboriginal groups he studied in central Australia as mere ‘magic’. By the 1960s, a new generation of anthropologists, influenced by Claude Levi-Strauss and English thinkers like E. Evans Pritchard, had arrived on the scene. This new ‘turn’ in anthropology led a number of contemporary scholars to the radical position that Western anthropology itself is a socio-cultural phenomenon that can be investigated in a broadly anthropological way. To see what this involves, it is worthwhile examining a number of crucial misunderstandings of Australian Aboriginal beliefs and practices that have been the artefactual result of various anthropological approaches.

Journal ArticleDOI
01 Feb 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors append the frame of dialectic upon St. John of the Cross' delineation of mysticism to unravel the web of relational concepts embedded within his immense writings on this unique phenomenon.
Abstract: This paper intends to append the frame of dialectic upon St. John of the Cross’ delineation of mysticism. Its underlying hypothesis is that the dialectical structuring of St. John’s mystical theology promises to unravel the web of relational concepts embedded within his immense writings on this unique phenomenon. It is hoped that as a consequence of this undertaking, relevant pairs of correlative opposites that figure prominently in mysticism can be elucidated and perhaps come to some form of resolution.

Journal ArticleDOI
02 Sep 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: This article propose a model of mystical development that is more subtle than traditional hierarchical models, and explain how the apparently differing accounts of Byzantine mystical development between traditions and thinkers can be reconciled with each other in a more convincing fashion.
Abstract: Critics have pointed out that the content and sequence of mystical development reported by different traditions do not seem very congruous with the contention that there is a universal path of mystical development. I propose a model of mystical development that is more subtle than traditional ‘invariant hierarchical’ models, and which explains how the apparently differing accounts of mystical development between traditions and thinkers can be reconciled with each other in a more convincing fashion, and brought together under one umbrella. The model preserves both the objective core of perennialism and the culturally subjective element of mystical ‘specialization’ that is undeniably evidenced in the mystical literature, and which hierarchical and invariant ‘universalist’ accounts struggle to integrate.

Journal ArticleDOI
16 Jan 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors argue that the atheistic critique of the Thomistic five ways, and similarly formulated cosmological arguments, argues at cross purposes because it misrepresents them.
Abstract: A number of recent discussions of atheism allude to cosmological arguments in support of theism. The five ways of Aquinas are classic instances, offered as rational justification for theistic belief. However, the five ways receive short shrift. They are curtly dismissed as vacuous, arbitrary, and even insulting to reason. I contend that the atheistic critique of the Thomistic five ways, and similarly formulated cosmological arguments, argues at cross purposes because it misrepresents them. I first lay out the context, intent and structure of Aquinas’ arguments, then show in what way recent discussions misrepresent them, and finally conclude with a comment on metaphysical orientation, which I take to be central, not only to a proper understanding of the Thomistic five ways but generally to the debate between atheism and theism on the existence of God.

Journal ArticleDOI
30 Jun 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this article, the authors propongo analizar la filosofia and intencion didactica del movimiento muralista mexicano de la primera mitad del siglo XX, asi como el papel de dicha filosophia en la trascendencia del mismo, tanto en el ambito artistico y culto de Mexico como en el popular.
Abstract: En este articulo me propongo analizar la filosofia e intencion didactica del movimiento muralista mexicano de la primera mitad del siglo XX, asi como el papel de dicha filosofia en la trascendencia del mismo, tanto en el ambito artistico y culto de Mexico como en el popular.

Journal ArticleDOI
16 Sep 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: A review article on Leszek Kolakowski's, "Why is there something rather than nothing?" centering on Leibniz's famous Question is presented in this paper, with a focus on the question itself.
Abstract: A review article on Leszek Kolakowski’s, ‘Why is There Something Rather Than Nothing?’ centering on Leibniz’s famous Question.


Journal ArticleDOI
13 Jan 2009-Sophia
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors discuss three important essays on the Annunciation and raise theological and phenomenological issues directly related to the almost unique iconic representation which Antonello gives us.
Abstract: Antonello da Messina’s Annunciation with the Blessed Virgin sola breaks with iconic convention, so inviting new interpretations of the theme. The Rome exhibition of 2006 allowed one to compare Antonello with van Eyck: Antonello seemed pre-modern. This review discusses three important essays on the Annunciation (see the last three keywords). All three perceptive essays raise theological and phenomenological issues directly related to the almost unique iconic representation which Antonello gives us.