scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessJournal ArticleDOI

Comments on Roger Cotterrell's Essay, 'The Struggle for Law: Some Dilemmas of Cultural Legality'

Reads0
Chats0
TLDR
Menkel-Meadow as mentioned in this paper argues that traditional Anglo-American jurisprudence has not sufficiently theorised the role of culture and cultures, and that multiculturalism renders inadequate, for different reasons, both Weberian and non-positivist or non-instrumental accounts of law.
Abstract
First, many thanks to Carrie Menkel-Meadow, the editors of The International Journal of Law In Context and the sponsors of this series for facilitating this lecture, and for inviting my participation. And a special thankyou to Professor Roger Cotterrell for sharing with us such a generous, humanistic and hopeful account of law’s moral possibilities, when faced with multicultural conflict within a society governed by a liberal rule of law.1 I very much appreciate the opportunity to reflect on this set of claims, although I feel somewhat an outsider to the task, as I’ll explain below. I understand Professor Cotterrell as arguing, first, that traditional Anglo-American jurisprudence has not sufficiently theorised the role of culture and cultures,2 second, that multiculturalism renders inadequate, for different reasons, both Weberian and non-positivist or non-instrumental accounts of law’s liberal aspirations,3 and third, that one possible way for law to contribute constructively to a moral and peaceful multicultural society would be to conceive of itself not just as an instrument for the fulfilment of private and conflicting individual purposes, not just as the target of passions from a more-or-less unified culture, but rather, as a means of respectful communication between cultures,4 albeit one that imposes individualist and liberal side-constraints on the conversation so fostered: to wit, that the law itself, and its parts, must be rigorously respectful of the autonomy and decency of all individuals, and must demand as much from citizens.5

read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Georgetown University Law Center Georgetown University Law Center
Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW
2009
Comments on Roger Cotterrell's Essay, 'The Struggle for Law: Comments on Roger Cotterrell's Essay, 'The Struggle for Law:
Some Dilemmas of Cultural Legality' Some Dilemmas of Cultural Legality'
Robin West
Georgetown University Law Center
, west@law.georgetown.edu
Georgetown Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 11-62
Copyright © 2009 Cambridge University Press; http://journals.cambridge.org/action/
displayJournal?jid=IJC
This paper can be downloaded free of charge from:
https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/590
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1847998
4 Int'l J.L. in Context 401-405 (2009)
This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author.
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub
Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal History Commons

Comments on Roger Cotterrells essay,
The struggle for law: some dilemmas
of cultural legality
Robin West
Georgetown University Law Center
First, many thanks to Carrie Menkel-Meadow, the editors of The International Journal of Law In Context
and the sponsors of this series for facilitating this lecture, and for inviting my participation. And a
special thankyou to Professor Roger Cotterrell for sharing with us such a generous, humanistic and
hopeful account of law’s moral possibilities, when faced with multicultural conflict within a society
governed by a liberal rule of law. I very much appreciate the opportunity to reflect on this set of
claims, although I feel somewhat an outsider to the task, as I’ll explain below. I understand Professor
Cotterrell as arguing, first, that traditional Anglo-American jurisprudence has not sufficiently
theorised the role of culture and cultures, second, that multiculturalism renders inadequate, for
different reasons, both Weberian and non-positivist or non-instrumental accounts of law’s liberal
aspirations, and third, that one possible way for law to contribute constructively to a moral and
peaceful multicultural society would be to conceive of itself not just as an instrument for the
fulfilment of private and conflicting individual purposes, not just as the target of passions from a
more-or-less unified culture, but rather, as a means of respectful communication between cultures,
albeit one that imposes individualist and liberal side-constraints on the conversation so fostered: to
wit, that the law itself, and its parts, must be rigorously respectful of the autonomy and decency of all
individuals, and must demand as much from citizens.
I am sympathetic to all three prongs of this project. I agree entirely that jurisprudence has
not well theorised the cultural; I agree that some of the strains in the general fac¸ ade of liberal
legalism are a result of multicultural forces and aspirations; and I am happy to share in the call
for legal doctrine that is civil and respectful. So in these comments, I will just voice some worries
about the overall thrust of the project, and offer some friendly amendments. The worries are
threefold: the first is jurisprudential, the second is political and the third might best be called
aspirational.
The jurisprudential worry is this: it may be the case, as Professor Cotterrell reminds us, that law is
importantly communicative, and as such communicates either well or poorly, ethically or not,
respectfully or not. It may well be true, as J. B. White has spent his career arguing,
1
that how we
use or abuse language in law says a great deal about our moral selves, that the communicative
function of law has much in common with the communicative function of the literary arts, that
both serve an ethical role in social life, that ethical speech in law is an ideal toward which we ought
strive. I do not mean to deny any of this. Nevertheless, adjudicative law, even if it is (or can be) a form
of ethical communication, is also the command of the sovereign. It is the wish of someone
with power imposed on someone with less. Yes, commands communicate, and ought to do so
respectfully. Commands also, though, do other things: they confiscate, they liberate, they empower
1 White (1984, 1985, 1990, 1991, 1994, 2003, 2006). Professor Cotterrell acknowledges his debt to White at
p. 380.
International Journal of Law in Context, 4,4 pp. 401–405 (2009) Cambridge University Press
doi: 10.1017/S1744552309004078 Printed in the United Kingdom

or dis-empower and they kill, more than occasionally. We need to heed the effects of this imperative
speech.
2
As we praise judges for their respectful, even ethical, uses of language, we need to attend to
the consequences of the commands that come sheathed in those respectful words. Is the command
lawful? Is it helpful? Is it a good thing, overall? The ethical words might change the world. The
command though will change the world. Is the change a just one? The virtues that we seek in our
communicative lives do not exhaust the virtues we should seek in our law. In adjudication as
elsewhere, the words should be respectful, and the speaker should speak ethically, be mindful of the
listener and seek to strengthen the bond of community that the language facilitates. Failure on that
score carries consequences. The command the words convey, though, must be just, and the new
world the command creates should constitute a change for the good. The integrity of the language it
employs, the ethical use of the words that constitute it and the communication thereby facilitated
none of that carries a guarantee that the force that is law’s core will be put to good use.
The second worry is political. In the 1950s, 1960s and 1970s liberal lawyers, Justices, and the
litigants whose causes they represented and adjudicated, went a long way in the United States toward
perfecting an individualist, liberal, formal, promise of equal justice between White and Black
citizens, and between women and men. The civil rights community, and the Justices that were a
part of it, did so, furthermore, through court opinions some of which were models of respect for the
individuality and decency of all citizens.
3
That moral accomplishment, we can now see, came with
some real costs, dangers and risks for progressive politics, which are familiar enough to this
audience,
4
and I will not belabour them, but I will mention just one. By perfecting, say, the
opportunities of women as well as men, of Blacks as well as Whites, to compete for jobs, or political
office, or the vote, etc., we court this risk: we invite a level of comfort regarding the overall justice of
our social world that may not be earned, and that may, in fact, be wildly misplaced. Bluntly: if it is no
longer true that Whites can discriminate against Blacks, that women or African-Americans can be
victimised by racist or sexist bigotry then the world seems to be a much fairer place. Since our
meritocracy now works is now true to its own promise we need not, in effect, concern ourselves
with the unequal outcomes of meritocratic competition on those who are on the bottom of our social
and economic pyramids. Self-congratulatory smugness of formal racial equality in some spheres, in
other words, might invite an undeserved, unearned complacency regarding social justice overall, and
particularly as it concerns poor people. If that is so, then the promised formal equality or formal
justice in the spheres of meritocratic competition comes with a pretty nasty kick: that formal justice
legitimates a huge and growing sphere of social injustice. If we think life is now fair since we do not
discriminate between White and Black, or men and women, or gays and straights, well then life is
2 I do not mean to suggest that legal positivism is at odds with Cotterrell’s (and White’s) understanding of
adjudication as communication; only that positivism highlights a feature of that communication its
imperative dimension that non-positivist theories of law tend to downplay. For classic treatments of
legal positivism, see, e.g., Austin (1861) and Bentham (1776). For a contemporary positivist conception
with a more nuanced (and rule-based) conception of legal imperativism at its core than that held by these
nineteenth-century theorists, see Hart (1994).
3 Brown v. Board of Education 347 U.S. 483 (1954) was a dramatic turnaround, not only in its holding, that de jure
segregation on the basis of race is unconstitutional, but also for its admirable tone of respect for minority
communities. More recently, the majority opinion in Lawrence v Texas 539 U.S. 558 (2003), in which the
Supreme Court held that states may not constitutionally criminalise consensual same-sex sexual conduct
between adults, and Justice Marshall’s opinion in Goodridge v. Mass. Dep. of Pub. Health, 440 Mass. 309, 798 N.
E.2d 941 (2003), in which the Massachusetts Supreme Court held that a ban on gay marriage violates the
Massachusetts Constitution, are also both civil rights victories and models of respectful communicative
adjudication.
4 Progressives now worry, rightly in my view, that the overreliance on civil rights litigation to achieve gains in
racial and sexual justice have come at the costs of ordinary progressive politics. We have come to view the
Courts, rather than the legislative branches, as the vehicle for just laws, and as a result our law has suffered.
I discuss this in detail in West (2008). See generally Rosenberg (1991), Tushnet (1999), Sager (2004).
robin west402

fair, at least so far as law is concerned. The growing gap between rich and poor, haves and have-nots,
economically privileged and underprivileged, is not morally problematic. It is the result of competi-
tion now made fair. It is not a problem. At least, it is not law’s problem.
American progressive legal academics worry a good deal about this dilemma,
5
so again, I won’t
belabour it. But let us not repeat it. The worry is just this: even if we could with a magic wand
transform our courts into conduits of respectful communication between Muslims, Fundamentalist
Protestants, Conservative Catholics and Orthodox Jews, that would not touch the growing divide
which is increasingly cultural, I would argue, at least on Cotterrell’s four-part definition of cultural
6
between those who live as those of us in this room live, and those whose lives are entirely different,
because severely impoverished. Professor Cotterrell made quick mention of this towards the start of his
paper, when he noted that Marx was the first of the difference theorists to posit a problem with the
assumption of a unified culture. But then the reference was dropped. Of course, we need not solve all
the world’s problems in every short paper. But we do need to worry that the gain in justice for which we
argue not come at the cost of a complacency regarding greater injustice. In this United States culture, at
this time, that strikes me as a very real worry. The cultural divide, here, that is proving devastating to
our decency is primarily economic not gender, race, ethnicity or religion-based. We need to worry
that the bridge we build between religious and ethnic cultures not unduly consume the energies for
social justice that might otherwise be free to address the elephant in the room and the elephant, in
brief, is class.
The third worry is closely related. Professor Cotterrell alluded to it indirectly in his paper, and
directly in responses to questions after his presentation. In the paper, Cotterrell suggests that our
liberal rule of law for the most part serves and recognises individuals and corporations. This leaves
human beings who are mightily constructed by, attached to, defined by and parts of culture, just a bit,
in the cold. Individuals and corporations, our jurisprudence sees. Encultured human beings not so
much so. But, Professor Cotterrell suggests, we could address this. Without abandoning the promise
of individualism, we can, and should, recognise encultured human beings they are individuals, too.
What we must do, then, is broaden, perhaps greatly, at least somewhat, our understanding of the
‘individualism’ that the liberal rule of law countenances. We might have to acknowledge that for
some cultures, ‘individual’ means something distinctive and we as a multitude need be respectful of
those differences.
Well, perhaps, and perhaps the broadening he suggests is a good one. But let me go back to square
one the observation that the liberal rule of law posits individuals and corporations as the object of
law’s solicitude and proffer a rather different worry, not addressed by the embrace of the encultured
human being as also being an individual worthy of law’s protection. The observation that the liberal
rule of law embraces individuals and corporations is extremely astute. It is also worrisome. Here in
the United States, the way it is often put is that the law respects ‘persons’ and then defines persons
so as to include both corporate and natural individuals. The implication of this sleight of hand is
clearly that corporations and natural individuals have some shared essence, or at least some shared
set of traits in common, that law can recognise. Whatever individuals and corporations both have in
common, then, becomes our definitional account of the ‘person’ that law recognises, protects, serves.
What might those traits be?
5 Much of the Critical Legal Studies movement from the 1970s on concerned these risks of ‘legitimation’ that
apparent gains in adjudicative justice would legitimate even greater economic or social injustices, and in
effect, be not worth the price. See Kairys (1998) and particularly the essays by Alan Freeman on race
discrimination law, and Robert Gordon on private law and contract law.
6 Culture, Cotterrell argues (this issue, p. 377), ‘in one aspect ...relates to shared beliefs or ultimate values; in
another, to matters of tradition, including common language, environment or historical experience. In a third
sense it refers to shared allegiances and emotions. In a fourth, it reflects levels of technological and productive
development (material culture) and instrumental (especially economic) social relationships.’
comments on roger cotterrell’s essay, ‘the struggle for law’ 403

Well, corporations maximise profit pretty much all the time, and individuals maximise utility at
least a good bit of the time. So, as the sun rises in the morning, the ‘person’ law protects, is,
increasingly, the utility maximiser. Again, however we define the individual law protects must be
by reference to traits shared by corporations, since corporations are also persons. Utility-maximiser
seems to be the shared ground, then, that law can readily identify. Utility-maximiser, then, is the
essence of personhood.
This is a problem for our law, for social justice and for the human beings that inhabit planet
earth. It is not solved by throwing cultures in the mix. Cultures also might well maximise profit,
or utility, who knows? Whether they are included, because they do so, or excluded because they
don’t, though, the larger problem, to my mind, is the continued lack of recognition of the fully
embodied, biological, animalistic human being that is borne in total dependency, lives for some
period of time, breathes, sickens, declines and dies. Corporations, and therefore the persons that
individuals are, do none of that. Persons, remember, must include corporations as well as
individuals, so the aspect of the individual protected by law, again, is not the born, breathing,
sickened, declining and dying animal. It may be the utility-maximising individual. It may be the
utility-maximising encultured individual. It is not the animal within us, much less the child
within of pop psychology. We need a jurisprudence for animals including the human animal. A
jurisprudence that embraces the culture, I worry, is not such a jurisprudence. It might well thicken
the person the law might imagine, see, recognise or valorize. But, with all due respect, a jurispru-
dence of culture will not thicken it all the way to the ground. It will not deliver us a jurisprudence
that respects our biological, physical, animalistic needs, our dependencies or our sicknesses unto
death. We need such a jurisprudence, I suspect, if we are to enliven, and lighten, either our finite
lives or the law that survives us.
References
austin, John (1861/1955), The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
bentham, Jeremy (1776/1976), A Comment on the Commentaries. Darmstadt: Scientia Verlag Aalen,
35–56, 60–74.
cotterrell, Roger (2008), ‘The Struggle for Law: Some Dilemmas of Cultural Legality’, International
Journal of Law In Context, 4(4): 373–84.
hart, H. L. A. (1994), The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
kairys, David (ed.) (1998) The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique. New York: Basic Books.
rosenberg, Gerald (1991), The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
sager, Lawrence (2004), Justice in Plainclothes: A Theory of American Constitutional Practice. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
tushnet, Mark (1999), Taking the Constitution Away from the Courts. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
west, Robin (2008), ‘Ennobling Politics’, in J. B. White (ed.) Resisting the Empire of Force. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 401–405.
white, James Boyd (1984) When Words Lose Their Meaning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
white, James Boyd (1985), Heracles’ Bow. Madison, WI: University of Madison Press.
white, James Boyd (1990), Justice as Translation: an Essay in Cultural and Legal Criticism. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
white, James Boyd (1994), Acts of Hope: Creating Authority in Literature, Law, and Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
robin west404

Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI

Law’s culture and lived culture: a comment on Roger Cotterrell’s ‘The struggle for law: some dilemmas of cultural legality’

TL;DR: Cotterrell and Menkel-Meadow as discussed by the authors discuss how law and legal theory might make sense of the legal demands of cultural pluralism in many pluralist societies.
Journal ArticleDOI

Culture, power and the human animal: a reply

TL;DR: In this paper, Mezey, John Mikhail and Robin West made a series of points about the place (or absence) of power in a picture of law's engagement with multiculturalism.
References
More filters
Book

The Concept of Law

H. L. A. Hart
TL;DR: The Foundations of a Legal System as mentioned in this paper is an example of a legal system based on formalism and rule-scepticism, and it can be seen as a union of primary and secondary rules.
Journal ArticleDOI

The hollow hope : can courts bring about social change?

TL;DR: Rosenberg's second edition of "The Hollow Hope" as mentioned in this paper was published in 2000, and it has been widely cited as a seminal work in political and social reform research.
Book

The Province of Jurisprudence Determined

J. L. Austin
TL;DR: The first professor of law at the University of London, John Austin (1790-1859) as mentioned in this paper, defined the term law as a set of rules laid down by political superiors for political inferiors in independent political societies.
Book

Taking the Constitution Away from the Courts

Mark Tushnet
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors put forward the idea of the creation of a constitutional law in which judicial declarations deserve no special consideration, citing the McCarthy incident in the 1950s as a prime example of how the judicial branch failed to enforce the will of the people.
Book

The politics of law : a progressive critique

David Kairys
TL;DR: Kairys as mentioned in this paper discusses the history of legal education and legal education as training for hierarchy in the United States and the role of law in women's subordination and women's empowerment.
Related Papers (5)
Frequently Asked Questions (10)
Q1. What did the liberal lawyers do in the 1950s and 1960s?

In the 1950s, 1960s and 1970s liberal lawyers, Justices, and the litigants whose causes they represented and adjudicated, went a long way in the United States toward perfecting an individualist, liberal, formal, promise of equal justice between White and Black citizens, and between women and men. 

In the paper, Cotterrell suggests that their liberal rule of law for the most part serves and recognises individuals and corporations. 

Without abandoning the promise of individualism, the authors can, and should, recognise encultured human beings – they are individuals, too. 

remember, must include corporations as well as individuals, so the aspect of the individual protected by law, again, is not the born, breathing, sickened, declining and dying animal. 

The civil rights community, and the Justices that were a part of it, did so, furthermore, through court opinions some of which were models of respect for the individuality and decency of all citizens. 

Self-congratulatory smugness of formal racial equality in some spheres, in other words, might invite an undeserved, unearned complacency regarding social justice overall, and particularly as it concerns poor people. 

Here in the United States, the way it is often put is that the law respects ‘persons’ – and then defines persons so as to include both corporate and natural individuals. 

Commands also, though, do other things: they confiscate, they liberate, they empower1 White (1984, 1985, 1990, 1991, 1994, 2003, 2006). 

The implication of this sleight of hand is clearly that corporations and natural individuals have some shared essence, or at least some shared set of traits in common, that law can recognise. 

I agree entirely that jurisprudence has not well theorised the cultural; The authoragree that some of the strains in the general façade of liberal legalism are a result of multicultural forces and aspirations; and The authoram happy to share in the call for legal doctrine that is civil and respectful.