scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessBook ChapterDOI

Milton Friedman's Stance: The Methodology of Causal Realism

TLDR
In this article, the authors try to reconcile Friedman's methodological writings with his practices as an empirical economist by, first, taking his roots in Alfred Marshall seriously and, second, by taking the methodological implications of his empirical work seriously.
Abstract
Milton Friedman is usually regarded as an instrumentalist on the basis of his infamous claim that economic theories are to be judged by their predictions and not by the realism of their assumptions This interpretation sits oddly with Friedman's empirical work - eg, Friedman and Schwartz''s monetary history - and his explicit rejection of theories of the business cycle that, while based on accurate correlations, nevertheless do not make economic sense In this paper, I try to reconcile Friedman's methodological writings with his practices as an empirical economist by, first, taking his roots in Alfred Marshall seriously and, second, by taking the methodological implications of his empirical work seriously Friedman dislikes the word "cause" Nevertheless, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding, Friedman is best understood as a causal realist - that is, one who understands the object of scientific inquiry as the discovery through empirical investigation of the true causal mechanisms underlying observable phenomena

read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Working Paper Series
Milton Friedman’s Stance: The Methodology of Causal
Realism
KevinHoover
UniversityofCalifornia,Davis
February01,2004
Paper#06-6
MiltonFriedmanisusuallyregardedasaninstrumentalistonthebasisofhis
infamousclaimthateconomictheoriesaretobejudgedbytheirpredictions
andnotbytherealismoftheirassumptions.Thisinterpretationsitsoddlywith
Friedman’sempiricalwork–e.g.,FriedmanandSchwartz’smonetaryhistory–
andhisexplicitrejectionoftheoriesofthebusinesscyclethat,whilebasedon
accuratecorrelations,neverthelessdonotmakeeconomicsense.Inthispaper,
ItrytoreconcileFriedman’smethodologicalwritingswithhispracticesasan
empiricaleconomistby,first,takinghisrootsinAlfredMarshallseriouslyand,
second,bytakingthemethodologicalimplicationsofhisempiricalwork
seriously.Friedmandislikestheword“cause”.Nevertheless,appearancestothe
contrarynotwithstanding,Friedmanisbestunderstoodasacausalrealist–that
is,onewhounderstandstheobjectofscientificinquiryasthediscovery
throughempiricalinvestigationofthetruecausalmechanismsunderlying
observablephenomena.
DepartmentofEconomics
OneShieldsAvenue
Davis,CA95616
(530)752-0741
http://www.econ.ucdavis.edu/working_search.cfm

Milton Friedman’s Stance:
The Methodology of Causal Realism
Kevin D. Hoover
Department of Economics
University of California
One Shields Avenue
Davis, California 95616-8578
Telephone + (530) 752-2129
Fax + (530) 752-9382
E-mail kdhoover@ucdavis.edu
Revised, 5 February 2004

1
Milton Friedman’s Stance: The Methodology of Causal Realism
I. The God of Abraham; the Methodology of Marshall
1
The philosopher Bas Van Fraassen opens his Terry Lectures (published as The Empirical
Stance) with an anecdote: “When Pascal died, a scrap of paper was found in the lining of
his coat. On it was written ‘The God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, not the God of the
philosophers’” (Van Fraassen 2002, p. 1). Pascal’s God talks and wrestles with men;
Descartes’ God is a creature of metaphysics. Analogously, with respect to the
“Methodology of Positive Economics,there are two Friedmans. Most of the gallons of
ink spilled in interpreting Friedman’s essay have treated it as a philosophical work. This
is true, for example, for those who have interpreted it as an exemplar of instrumentalism,
Popperian falsificationism, conventionalism, positivism and so forth. And it is even true
for those critics, such as Samuelson (1963), whose credentials as an economist are
otherwise secure. Mayer (1993, 1995, 2003), and Hands (2003) remind us that Friedman
was philosophically unsophisticated, and in the essay Friedman tried a fall with other
economists, not with philosophers. The origin of the essay was the quotidian practice of
economics, not abstract epistemology. To know the Friedman of the economists, I
propose to read the essay in light of Friedman (and Schwartz’s) A Monetary History of
the United States, 1867-1960 (1963a) and “Money and Business Cycles” (1963b),
perhaps his most characteristic economic investigations.
1
I thank Uskali Mäki, Thomas Mayer, and the participants in the F53 Conference at the Erasmus Institute
of Philosophy and Economics, Rotterdam 12-13 December 2003 for comments on an earlier draft. I also
thank Ryan Brady for research assistance. J. Daniel Hammond (1996) wrote an important book that
examines Friedman’s economic thought from a causal perspective. While I intentionally did not reread that
book in trying to develop my own views somewhat independently, I could not help but be influenced by it.

2
My point is not that there is a particular philosophers’ position that can be
contrasted with a particular economists’ (or even Friedman’s) position. After all, Pascal
surely recognized that there were a variety of views of God among the philosophers. Nor
would I suggest that philosophy has nothing valuable to say about, or learn from,
Friedman’s essay; nor Friedman about or from philosophy. It is rather a matter of
approach. Friedman cares most about doing economics and is largely innocent of the
interests of philosophers and, equally, of the distinctions and nuances that philosophers
routinely employ. If we either as economists or philosophers insist on reading the
essay as a philosophical work addressed to philosophers, we must misread it.
The most infamous passage in Friedman’s essay runs: “Truly important and
significant hypotheses will be found to have ‘assumptions’ that are wildly inaccurate
descriptive representations of reality, and, in general, the more significant the theory, the
more unrealistic the assumptions (in this sense)” (p. 14).
2
Samuelson (1963, pp. 232-
233) sees this as the extreme version of Friedman’s general proposition that “[a] theory is
vindicated if (some of) its consequences are empirically valid to a useful degree of
approximation; the (empirical) realism of the theory ‘itself,’ or of its ‘assumptions,’ is
quite irrelevant to its validity and worth,” which he stigmatizes with the shorthand F-
twist.
3
The view that Friedman does not care about the truth of the assumptions faces a
serious difficulty. After recounting the detailed evidence on the cyclical behavior of
2
Except where context would render it ambiguous, references to Friedman (1953) will be referred to
hereinafter by page numbers without dates.
3
Replacing Friedman by his initial is an indication that Samuelson (1963, p. 232) is aware that the F-twist
may be “a misinterpretation of [Friedman’s] intention.” While Samuelson rails against Friedman’s
apparent abandonment of truth and realism, Frazier and Boland (1983) turn it into a positive virtue. They
interpret Friedman as an instrumentalist and defend instrumentalism as a logically sound doctrine. My
suggestion here is that they have misinterpreted Friedman he is not an instrumentalist and my
suggestion in Hoover (1984) is that Frazer and Boland’s version of instrumentalism is not sound doctrine.

3
money and the real economy, Friedman and Schwartz (1963b, pp. 213-214) raises the
question, how we can be sure about the direction of influence?
It might be, so far as we know, that one could marshal a similar body of evidence
demonstrating that the production of dressmakers’ pins has displayed over the past
nine decades a regular cyclical pattern; that the pin pattern reaches a peak well
before the reference peak and a trough well before the reference trough; that its
amplitude is highly correlated with the amplitude of the movements in general
business. It might even be demonstrated that the simple correlation between the
production of pins and consumption is higher than the simple correlation between
autonomous expenditures and consumption; that the partial correlation between
pins and consumption holding autonomous expenditure constant is as high as
the simple correlation; and that the correlation between consumption and
autonomous expenditures holding the production of pins constant is on the
average zero. . . [B]ut even if [these statements] were demonstrated beyond a
shadow of a doubt, they would persuade neither us nor our readers to adopt a pin
theory of the cycle.
But why not? In Friedman and Schwartz’s thought experiment, the pin theory of the
cycle has implications that are confirmed facts. Why should the same variety of evidence
that supports a monetary theory not equally well support a pin theory? “Primarily, the
difference is that we have other kinds of evidence” (Friedman and Schwartz 1963b, p.
214): (i) pins are a trifling element in the economy, and “[w]e expect the effect to be in
rough proportion to the cause”, but money is pervasive in economies that experience
business cycles; (ii) with money we can, and with pins we cannot, conceive of channels
through which large autonomous changes in them might affect the economy; (iii) in
contrast to a monetary theory, no serious student of business cycles has ever seriously
suggested a pin theory.
It is not good enough for Friedman that a pin theory implies the facts. His
criticisms are based on evidence relevant to the truth of its assumptions. The Monetary
History can be seen as a detailed marshalling, not only of the facts implied by Friedman’s
monetary theory, but of the evidence for the truth of its underlying mechanisms and

Citations
More filters

The Dappled World

Abstract: The Dappled World is not only, as the subtitle says, A Study of the Boundaries of Science ; it is also a study of the boundaries of natural law. From my empiricist point of view the two are intimately connected. The best way to learn about laws of nature is by looking at the laws of our most successful and admired sciences. I focus on the exact sciences, in particular on physics and economics. I do not look at biology, geology, anthropology, sociology or any of the other natural or social sciences. Superficially it looks as if they should be more, rather than less, open to the kind of interpretation I give; still, they may teach different or additional lessons. The central thesis is what Peter Lipton here calls “anomalous dappling”. Laws of nature (if conceived of as necessary or counterfactual regularities between so-called ‘occurrent properties’) are limited in their range; in regions that seem to overlap, the separate laws may be helpful in calculating what happens, but the overall outcome may be highly context dependent or there may be no rules at all for composing the separate effects; and some situations may not be subject to law at all—what happens happens by hap. I give three major arguments in favour of dappling. As with many philosophical views, a first step is to show that the view is possible. So one of my central aims is to show that dappling is consistent with our most impressive scientific successes and that it is consistent with realism— that is, it may be true even of the set of all nature’s ‘true’ laws. 1
Book ChapterDOI

Dr. Keynes: economic theory in a diagnostic science

TL;DR: For example, of the ten volumes of books published in his lifetime, three (the General Theory and the two volumes of the Treatise on Money, volume I subtitled The Pure Theory of Money and volume II The Applied Theory of money ) feature 'theory' in their title as mentioned in this paper.
Posted Content

The Two Blades of Occam's Razor in Economics: Logical and Heuristic

TL;DR: The use of Occam's razor in the economic debate around realism in economic modelling has been discussed in this article, where the authors show that it can be used as a principle of logic that emphasises simplicity, or as a heuristic tool that emphasizes parsimony.
Journal ArticleDOI

Did Milton Friedman's methodology license the Formalist Revolution?

TL;DR: The authors examines two conflicting views that have emerged within the recent methodological literature regarding the relationship between Friedman's famous essay and the formalist revolution, and focuses on three influential contributors to this ongoing debate: Mark Blaug, Terence Hutchison, and Thomas Mayer.

Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

TL;DR: In this article, the authors present a reflection on the archives of contemporary life sciences and present a set of issues in respect to the available sources, including the use of historical sources, digital sources, material artefacts, and oral sources.
References
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI

Statistics and Causal Inference

TL;DR: In this article, the authors use a particular model for causal inference (Holland and Rubin 1983; Rubin 1974) to critique the discussions of other writers on causation and causal inference.
Book

A Monetary History of the United States

TL;DR: The long-awaited monetary history of the United States by Friedman and Schwartz is in every sense of the term a monumental scholarly achievement as discussed by the authors, and the treatment of innumerable issues, large and small, have been brought to bear on the solution of complex and subtle economic issues.
Posted Content

A Monetary History of the United States, 1867–1960

TL;DR: The long-awaited monetary history of the United States by Friedman and Schwartz is in every sense of the term a monumental scholarly achievement -monumental in its sheer bulk, monumental in definitiveness of its treatment of innumerable issues, large and small... monumental, above all, in the theoretical and statistical effort and ingenuity that have been brought to bear on the solution of complex and subtle economic issues as discussed by the authors.
Book

The Philosophy of Logical Atomism

TL;DR: The Philosophy of Logical Atomism (1918) as discussed by the authors ) is a philosophy of logic at the level of logical atomism, with a focus on atomic and molecular positions.
Frequently Asked Questions (8)
Q1. What have the authors contributed in "Milton friedman’s stance: the methodology of causal realism" ?

Milton Friedman is usually regarded as an instrumentalist on the basis of his infamous claim that economic theories are to be judged by their predictions and not by the realism of their assumptions. This interpretation sits oddly with Friedman ’ s empirical work – e. g., Friedman and Schwartz ’ s monetary history – and his explicit rejection of theories of the business cycle that, while based on accurate correlations, nevertheless do not make economic sense. In this paper, I try to reconcile Friedman ’ s methodological writings with his practices as an empirical economist by, first, taking his roots in Alfred Marshall seriously and, second, by taking the methodological implications of his empirical work seriously. 

The essence of Friedman’s Marshallian stance is that the pursuit of substantiveknowledge cannot be stymied by the incompleteness and, therefore, “unrealism” of theory. 

In his interview with Hammond (1992, p. 92), Friedman said: “The problem that bothers me about cause is that it almost invariably leads into a problem of infinite regress. 

The problem with talking about causes is that, working backwards in time, the chain never ends and, working contemporaneously, the array of causes is (perhaps infinitely) wide. 

Friedman routinely employs a large varietyof synonyms and circumlocutions, so that he clearly engages in causal talk, even when explicit causal words are not in play. 

All the authors can do is to work back and forth between theory and facts, starting with the primitive and highly tentative and working towards the sophisticated and more secure. 

But The authorhave argued at length elsewhere that the fall and rise of causal usage is connected to the rise and fall of formalism in econometrics, which is itself closely connected to the rise and fall of formalism in economics generally (Hoover 2004) . 

“[T]he most reckless and treacherous of all theorists is he who professes to let the facts and figures speak for themselves . . . ” (p. 168; cf. Friedman 1949, p. 90).