scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessJournal ArticleDOI

What "patient-centered care" requires in serious cultural conflict.

Autumn Fiester
- 01 Jan 2012 - 
- Vol. 87, Iss: 1, pp 20-24
TLDR
The author examines the tension that occurs when culturally sensitive patient-centered care disrupts the workflow of the service, requires acknowledging antithetical, unsupportable values, or entails discriminatory or ad hominem practices that constitute a personal insult or affront to the provider.
Abstract
The medical community has hailed the recent movement to provide patient-centered care as a progressive step forward in meeting the needs of the very diverse patient population of the United States. Stakeholders in all arenas of U.S. medicine-professional organizations, public advocacy groups, hospital administration, medical school leadership, insurance carriers, and nursing-have embraced the focus on patient-centered care. But, although the community universally endorses the ideal of patient-centered care, the ethical obligations it entails have only just begun to be explored. One of the most difficult circumstances in which to provide patient-centered care is when there is a deep cultural conflict-that is, when the values and priorities of the patient and his or her family are in direct opposition to those of the clinical team. Given the mandate to provide care that is "culturally and linguistically appropriate," the author asks what obligations providers have to meet patient demands when doing so is inconvenient, challenging, or, at the extreme, offensive and contrary to clinical values. The author examines the tension that occurs when culturally sensitive patient-centered care disrupts the workflow of the service, requires acknowledging antithetical, unsupportable values, or entails discriminatory or ad hominem practices that constitute a personal insult or affront to the provider. The strategy the author has invoked for this analysis is to search for common values that might provide a bridge between patients and providers who are in deep cultural conflict.

read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

"2-:)67-8=3*)227=0:%2-%"2-:)67-8=3*)227=0:%2-%
',30%60=311327 ',30%60=311327
)28)6*36-3)8,-'7%4)67 )28)6*36-3)8,-'7

#,%8%8-)28)28)6)(%6))59-6)7-2 )6-39790896%032C-'8#,%8%8-)28)28)6)(%6))59-6)7-2 )6-39790896%032C-'8
98912-)78)6
"2-:)67-8=3*)227=0:%2-%
B)78)61%-01)(94)22)(9
3003;8,-7%2(%((-8-32%0;36/7%8,88476)437-836=94)22)(9&-3)8,-'7$4%4)67
%683*8,)-3)8,-'7%2()(-'%08,-'7311327
)'311)2()(-8%8-32)'311)2()(-8%8-32
-)78)6#,%8%8-)28)28)6)(%6))59-6)7-2 )6-39790896%032C-'8
'%()1-')(-'-2)

,884(<(3-36+&)%'&
!,-7-7%232B2%0:)67-323*%2%68-'0)49&0-7,)(-2B2%0*361-2
'%()1-')(-'-2)

!,-74%4)6-74378)(%8 ',30%60=311327,88476)437-836=94)22)(9&-3)8,-'7$4%4)67
36136)-2*361%8-3240)%7)'328%'86)437-836=43&3<94)22)(9

#,%8%8-)28)28)6)(%6))59-6)7-2 )6-39790896%032C-'8#,%8%8-)28)28)6)(%6))59-6)7-2 )6-39790896%032C-'8
&786%'8&786%'8
!,)6)')2813:)1)2883463:-()@4%8-)28')28)6)('%6)A,%7&))2,%-0)(%7%463+6)77-:)78)4*36;%6(-2
1))8-2+8,)2))(73*8,):)6=(-:)67)4%8-)2843490%8-323*8,)"2-8)( 8%8)7!,)*3'97324%8-)28
')28)6)('%6),%7&))2)1&6%')(%8%000):)073*1)6-'%21)(-'-2)463*)77-32%036+%2->%8-32749&0-'
%(:3'%'=+63947,374-8%0%(1-2-786%83671)(-'%07',3300)%()67,-4-2796%2')'%66-)67%2(2967-2+
7',330798;,-0)8,)-()%03*4%8-)28')28)6)('%6)-792-:)67%00=)2(367)(8,))8,-'%03&0-+%8-327-8
)28%-07,%:)320=&)+9283&))<4036)(2)3*8,)1378(-D'908'-6'9178%2')7-2;,-',83463:-()
4%8-)28')28)6)('%6)-7-2())4'90896%0'32C-'8;,)6)8,):%09)7%2(46-36-8-)73*8,)4%8-)28%6)-2(-6)'8
34437-8-32838,37)3*8,)'0-2-'%08)%1-:)28,)1%2(%8)83463:-()'%6)8,%8-7@'90896%00=%2(
0-2+9-78-'%00=%446346-%8)A8,)%98,36%7/7;,%83&0-+%8-327463:-()67,%:)831))84%8-)28()1%2(7;,)2
-8-7-2'32:)2-)28',%00)2+-2+36%88,))<86)1)3**)27-:)%2(%28-8,)8-'%0831%-2786)%1:%09)7%6-)67
%6))<%1-2)(8,%84%8-)28')28)6)('%6)-279','%7)7-7(-76948-:)838,);36/C3;3*8,)7)6:-')
6)59-6)7%'/23;0)(+)1)283*-00)+-8-1%8):%09)736)28%-07(-7'6-1-2%836=46%'8-')78,%8'3278-898)%
4)6732%0-2790836%**6328838,)463:-()6!,)786%8)+=-2:3/)(*368,-7%2%0=7-7-7%7)%6',*36'31132
:%09)78,%81-+,8463:-()%&6-(+)&)8;))24%8-)287%2(463:-()67-2())4'90896%0'32C-'8!,)%98,36
'32'09()7&=6)7432(-2+838,)7)-14368%28&%66-)6783463:-(-2+4%8-)28')28)6)('%6)
)=;36(7)=;36(7
&-3)8,-'7'0-2-'%0)8,-'71)(-'%0)8,-'7
-7'-40-2)7-7'-40-2)7
-3)8,-'7%2()(-'%08,-'7?)(-'-2)%2()%08, '-)2')7
311)287311)287
!,-7-7%232B2%0:)67-323*%2%68-'0)49&0-7,)(-2B2%0*361-2
'%()1-')(-'-2)

!,-7.3962%0%68-'0)-7%:%-0%&0)%8 ',30%60=311327,88476)437-836=94)22)(9&-3)8,-'7$4%4)67

1
What “Patient-Centered Care” Requires in Serious Cultural Conflict
Autumn Fiester, PhD
Dr. Fiester is the Associate Director of the University of Pennsylvania Center for
Bioethics and the Director of Graduate Studies in the Department of Medical Ethics at the
University of Pennsylvania School of Medicine.
Autumn Fiester, PhD
Center for Bioethics
3401 Market Street
Suite 320
Philadelphia, PA 19104
Phone: (215) 573-2602
Fax: (215) 573-3036
fiester@mail.med.upenn.edu
No external funding to report.

2
Abstract
The recent movement to provide “patient-centered care” has been hailed as a
progressive step forward in meeting the needs of the very diverse patient population of
the United States. The focus on patient-centered care has been embraced at all levels of
American medicine: professional organizations, public advocacy groups, hospital
administrators, medical school leadership, insurance carriers, and nursing schools. But
while the ideal of patient-centered care is universally endorsed, the ethical obligations it
entails have only begun to be explored. One of the most difficult circumstances in
which to provide patient-centered care is in deep cultural conflict, where the values and
priorities of the patient are in direct opposition to those of the clinical team. Given the
mandate to provide care that is “culturally and linguistically appropriate,” the author asks
what obligations providers have to meet patient demands when it is inconvenient,
challenging, or, at the extreme, offensive and antithetical to mainstream values.
Bariers are examined that patient-centered care in such cases is disruptive to the
work-flow of the service, requires acknowledgement of illegitimate values, or entails
discriminatory practices that constitute a personal insult or affront to the provider. The
strategy invoked for this analysis is a search for common values that might provide a
bridge between patients and providers in deep cultural conflict. The author concludes by
responding to these important barriers to providing patient-centered care.

3
What “Patient-Centered Care” Requires in Serious Cultural Conflict
Consider the impasse between the patient and the clinician in the following case:
A male radiologist is called by the ED to perform an evaluation for an
intra-uterine pregnancy. The patient has come to the ED with bleeding and
abdominal pain. The patient's beta-HCG is around 250. When the radiologist
arrives in the patient’s room, he finds her covered in a burqa, and the patient's
husband explains that she needs to remain covered and that the male radiologist
will not be allowed to perform the necessary exam. The patient says nothing.
There appears to be no language barrier.
In the context of the recent movement to provide “patient-centered care,” cases like this
one present a serious challenge to the clinical team: what the patient – or at least the
person speaking for the patient – considers necessary for her values to be protected is in
direct conflict not only with the standard of care, but with the standard operating
procedures in contemporary US medical settings. The standard of care in a suspected
ectopic pregnancy is a diagnostic vaginal ultrasound, and the standard operating
procedure is that the clinician assigned to the case (of whatever gender) does the exam
and the exam is performed in a hospital gown. Against the backdrop of the already
almost unmanageable clinical load in US emergency departments, what type of attention
and accommodation does “patient-centered care” demand when that effort threatens to

Citations
References
More filters
BookDOI

Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals

TL;DR: Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals from 1785 is one of the most important and influential texts in the whole history of philosophy as mentioned in this paper, its central purpose is to develop the categorical imperative.
Journal ArticleDOI

Medicine, rationality, and experience: an anthropological perspective.

TL;DR: Books and internet are the recommended media to help you improving your quality and performance.
Journal ArticleDOI

Informed Consent, Cultural Sensitivity, and Respect for Persons

TL;DR: The doctrine of informed consent to medical treatment or research is grounded in the ethical principle of respect for persons that regards individuals as autonomous agents "capable of deliberation about personal goals and of acting under the direction of such deliberation."
Journal ArticleDOI

Opening cultural doors: Providing culturally sensitive healthcare to Arab American and American Muslim patients

TL;DR: Insight into the behaviors, requirements, and preferences of Arab American and American Muslim patients, especially as they apply to women's health are offered.
Journal ArticleDOI

Cultural competence and the culture of medicine.

TL;DR: Renee Fox writes that most considerations of cultural competence neither identify nor explore the culture of medical training grounds.
Related Papers (5)
Frequently Asked Questions (9)
Q1. What are the contributions in "What "Patient-Centered Care" requires in serious cultural conflict" ?

The recent movement to provide “ patient-centered care ” has been hailed as a progressive step forward in meeting the needs of the very diverse patient population of the United States. One of the most difficult circumstances in which to provide patient-centered care is in deep cultural conflict, where the values and priorities of the patient are in direct opposition to those of the clinical team. Given the mandate to provide care that is “ culturally and linguistically appropriate, ” the author asks what obligations providers have to meet patient demands when it is inconvenient, challenging, or, at the extreme, offensive and antithetical to mainstream values. Bariers are examined that patient-centered care in such cases is disruptive to the work-flow of the service, requires acknowledgement of illegitimate values, or entails discriminatory practices that constitute a personal insult or affront to the provider. The strategy invoked for this analysis is a search for common values that might provide a bridge between patients and providers in deep cultural conflict. The author concludes by responding to these important barriers to providing patient-centered care. 

Given the American commitment to religious pluralism and tolerance, if one religious orcultural belief or value is deemed legitimate and worthy of respect, then their default position must be that they all are. 

My response to this objection (perhaps controversially) is that ignoring or dismissing the couple’s request request is tantamount to being complicit in a kind of psychological or emotional assault, so concerns about discrimination must yield here. 

Protecting her need for a high level of bodily privacy means working with her tominimize the amount of bodily exposure she has and controlling the gender of the providers she comes in contact with. 

The third feature of the cultural differences that the authors routinely accommodate is thatthey are not (3) ad hominem with regard to the provider: the requests do not discriminate against certain categories of providers by race, gender, sexual orientation, etc. 

And while it is laudatory that the authors respect the value of this religious group, it is also the case that there are somewhere between two and five times as many American Muslims (the religious subgroup that might don a burqa) as American Jehovah’s Witnesses. 

So one lesson to draw about their ability to meet patient needs in cases of cultural or religious difference is that when demands are relatively novel, they may cause interruption in a way that they might not, once a standard method for handling them is developed; the authors can’t refuse accommodation merely because a system for accommodating that request hasn’t yet been worked out. 

The second feature of the patient-demands the authors routinely accommodate is that theyare not considered (2) illegitimate, but are implicitly sanctioned as worthy of thataccommodation. 

I want to look at three values that The authorwill claim are universal and merely instantiated (or cashed out) differently: autonomy, informed consent, and bodily privacy.