scispace - formally typeset
Search or ask a question

Showing papers in "The Philosophical Quarterly in 2021"


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny as discussed by the authors by Manne Kate, published by Oxford University Press, 2017. Pp. 368. Price £20.99 £15.99.
Abstract: Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny. By Manne Kate. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017. Pp. 368. Price £20.99.)

261 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The authors identify a theoretical and political role for white ignorance, present three alternative accounts of white ignorance and assess how well each fulfils this role, and argue that, because of its greater power and flexibility, the Structuralist View better explains the patterns of ignorance that we observe, better illuminates the connection to white racial domination, and is overall better suited to the project of ameliorating racial injustice.
Abstract: In this paper, I identify a theoretical and political role for ‘white ignorance’, present three alternative accounts of white ignorance, and assess how well each fulfils this role. On the Willful Ignorance View, white ignorance refers to white individuals’ willful ignorance about racial injustice. On the Cognitivist View, white ignorance refers to ignorance resulting from social practices that distribute faulty cognitive resources. On the Structuralist View, white ignorance refers to ignorance that (1) results as part of a social process that systematically gives rise to racial injustice, and (2) is an active player in the process. I argue that, because of its greater power and flexibility, the Structuralist View better explains the patterns of ignorance that we observe, better illuminates the connection to white racial domination, and is overall better suited to the project of ameliorating racial injustice. As such, the Structuralist View should be preferred.

258 citations




Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the main function of mathematical justification is to guarantee that the mathematical community can correct the errors that inevitably arise from our fallible practices, i.e., cognitively diligent, well-functioning mathematicians go wrong.
Abstract: According to the received view, genuine mathematical justification derives from proofs. In this article, I challenge this view. First, I sketch a notion of proof that cannot be reduced to deduction from the axioms but rather is tailored to human agents. Secondly, I identify a tension between the received view and mathematical practice. In some cases, cognitively diligent, well-functioning mathematicians go wrong. In these cases, it is plausible to think that proof sets the bar for justification too high. I then propose a fallibilist account of mathematical justification. I show that the main function of mathematical justification is to guarantee that the mathematical community can correct the errors that inevitably arise from our fallible practices.

14 citations



Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, the authors argue that aesthetic reasons can demand actions, not merely justify them, and that there are aesthetic obligations to act, not only permissions, and conclude that the aesthetic asks little of us as patients and much of as agents.
Abstract: What does the aesthetic ask of us? What claims do the aesthetic features of the objects and events in our environment make on us? My answer in this paper is: that depends. Aesthetic reasons can only justify feelings – they cannot demand them. A corollary of this is that there are no aesthetic obligations to feel, only permissions. However, I argue, aesthetic reasons can demand actions – they do not merely justify them. A corollary of this is that there are aesthetic obligations to act, not only permissions. So, I conclude, the aesthetic asks little of us as patients and much of as agents.

12 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This paper provides a new argument against what is probably the most popular variant of expected utility maximization: causal decision theory (CDT), and provides two scenarios in which CDT voluntarily loses money.
Abstract: Newcomb’s problem has spawned a debate about which variant of expected utility maximisation (if any) should guide rational choice. In this paper, we provide a new argument against what is probably the most popular variant: causal decision theory (CDT). In particular, we provide two scenarios in which CDT voluntarily loses money. In the first, an agent faces a single choice and following CDT’s recommendation yields a loss of money in expectation. The second scenario extends the first to a diachronic Dutch book against CDT.

11 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, a critique of the idea that whether values will help us to live can serve as a criterion for choosing which values to choose to live by is presented, arguing that the project must either fall prey to the Saint Just's illusion or fall back into the problems it was supposed to escape.
Abstract: Amplifying Bernard Williams’ critique of the Nietzschean project of a revaluation of values, this paper mounts a critique of the idea that whether values will help us to live can serve as a criterion for choosing which values to live by. I explore why it might not serve as a criterion and highlight a number of further difficulties faced by the Nietzschean project. I then come to Nietzsche's defence, arguing that if we distinguish valuations from values, there is at least one form of the project which overcomes those difficulties. Finally, however, I show that even on this reading, the project must either fall prey to ‘Saint-Just's illusion’ or fall back into the problems it was supposed to escape. This highlights important difficulties faced by the Nietzschean project and its descendants while also explaining why Williams, who was so Nietzschean in other respects, remained wary of the revaluation of values as a project.

8 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors cast doubt on a proposed obligation to seek the permission of co-actors before exiting a collective action, and suggest instead that this obligation is a function of explicit promising.
Abstract: What do we owe each other when we act together? According to normativists about collective action, necessarily something and potentially quite a bit. They contend that collective action inherently involves a special normative status amongst participants, which may, for example, involve mutual obligations to receive the concurrence of the others before leaving. We build on recent empirical work whose results lend plausibility to a normativist account by further investigating the specific package of mutual obligations associated with collective action according to our everyday understanding. However, our results cast doubt on a proposed obligation to seek the permission of co-actors before exiting a collective action, and suggest instead that this obligation is a function of explicit promising. We then discuss how our results pave the path for a new normativism, a theory that neither undernor overshoots the target given by our common conception of the interpersonal obligations present in collective action.

7 citations


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The authors provide a Neo-Lewisian account of subject matter, which retains all the virtues of Lewis' but also includes an attractive characterisation of sentential subject matter. But it does not address the question of whether a sentence of a given language can be considered a subject subject.
Abstract: The notion of subject matter is a key concern of contemporary philosophy of language and logic. A central task for a theory of subject matter is to characterise the notion of sentential subject matter, that is, to assign to each sentence of a given language a subject matter that may count as its subject matter. In this paper, we elaborate upon David Lewis’ account of subject matter. Lewis’ proposal is simple and elegant but lacks a satisfactory characterisation of sentential subject matter. Drawing on linguistic literature on focus and on the question under discussion, we offer a neo-Lewisian account of subject matter, which retains all the virtues of Lewis’ but also includes an attractive characterisation of sentential subject matter.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The authors argue that some forms of non-ideal metalinguistic disagreement are deeply worrying, and they identify a distinctive wrong that occurs when one speaker has greater control in the joint activity of pairing contents with words in a context.
Abstract: In this paper, I explain the kinematics of non-ideal metalinguistic disagreement. This occurs when one speaker has greater control in the joint activity of pairing contents with words in a context. I argue that some forms of non-ideal metalinguistic disagreement are deeply worrying. When we pay attention to certain power imbalances in such exchanges, we are able to locate a distinctive wrong. This occurs when a speaker possesses illegitimate control in metalinguistic disagreement owing to the operation of identity prejudice. I call this metalinguistic injustice. The wrong involves restricting a speaker from participating in the processes that determine the epistemic/linguistic resources of a conversation, and/or undermining a speaker’s ability to affect metalinguistic outcomes.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: Causal determinism is the thesis that every event and action, including human action, is the inevitable result of proceeding events and actions in conjunction with the laws of nature as discussed by the authors.
Abstract: Causal determinism is the thesis that every event and action, including human action, is the inevitable result of proceeding events and actions in conjunction with the laws of nature. Besides the usual threats that causal determinism poses to free will and basic desert moral responsibility (see Pereboom 2001, 2014; Caruso 2012, 2021), some philosophers maintain that belief in the truth of causal determinism also poses a threat to rational deliberation (see, e.g. Taylor 1966; Ginet 1966; Kant 1785/1981; Haji 2012). Those who find this threat illusory are deliberationcompatibilists:1

Journal ArticleDOI
Adam Bradley1
TL;DR: The Embodied View as mentioned in this paper is a novel metaphysical account on which pains are constitutively mind-dependent features of parts of a subject's body, such as a location in the body, and mental characteristics such as being mind-independent.
Abstract: Bodily pain strikes many philosophers as deeply paradoxical. The issue is that pains seem to bear both physical characteristics, such as a location in the body, and mental characteristics, such being mind-dependent. In this paper I clarify and address this alleged paradox of pain. I begin by showing how a further assumption, Objectivism, the thesis that what one feels in one’s body when one is in pain is something mind-independent, is necessary for the generation of the paradox. Consequently, the paradox can be avoided if one rejects this idea. However, doing so raises its own difficulties, for it is not obvious how anything can possess all of the features we typically associate with bodily pain. To address this puzzle and finally put the paradox of pain to rest, I develop the Embodied View, a novel metaphysical account on which pains are constitutively mind-dependent features of parts of a subject’s body.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The authors argue that the success of this argument rests on the claim that mathematical explanations locate pure mathematical facts on which their physical explananda depend, and that any account of mathematical explanation that supports this claim fails to provide an adequate understanding of mathematical explanations.
Abstract: Some scientific explanations appear to turn on pure mathematical claims. The enhanced indispensability argument appeals to these ‘mathematical explanations’ in support of mathematical platonism. I argue that the success of this argument rests on the claim that mathematical explanations locate pure mathematical facts on which their physical explananda depend, and that any account of mathematical explanation that supports this claim fails to provide an adequate understanding of mathematical explanation. Words: 8,142 (not including bibliography).

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This paper argued that the quest for the one true metasemantics might be a Quixotic one, and argued that there is still significant scope for meta-semantic theorizing.
Abstract: What determines the meaning of a context-sensitive expression in a context? It is standardly assumed that, for a given expression type, there will be a unitary answer to this question; most of the literature on the subject involves arguments designed to show that one particular metasemantic proposal is superior to a specific set of alternatives. The task of the present essay will be to explore whether this is a warranted assumption, or whether the quest for the one true metasemantics might be a Quixotic one. We argue that there are good reasons—much better than are commonly appreciated—for thinking the latter, but that there nevertheless remains significant scope for metasemantic theorizing. We conclude by outlining our preferred option, metasemantic pluralism.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This article proposed a taxonomy of fictional truths based on the assumption that more is true in a work of fiction than explicitly said, and showed that this taxonomy overlooks an important class of fictional truth: those generated by literary formal features.
Abstract: It is widely agreed that more is true in a work of fiction than explicitly said. In addition to directly stipulated fictional content (explicit truth), inference and background assumptions give us implicit truths. However, this taxonomy of fictional truths overlooks an important class of fictional truth: those generated by literary formal features. Fictional works generate fictional content by both semantic and formal means, and content arising from formal features such as italics or font size are neither explicit nor implicit: not explicit since formal features don’t say anything; and not implicit since content generated from formal features doesn’t rely on other truths or background assumptions. In addition to showing that our current classification is incomplete, the new class of fictional truths provides four further upshots for definitions of fictional truth, story and work identity conditions, and the relationship between literary interpretation and fictional truth.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors construct the most plausible defence of the benefit argument and defend it against a possible objection, and then they consider how their argument would be affected were the standard account revised in an attempt to evade the so-called pre-emption problem.
Abstract: Some suggest that gene editing human embryos to prevent genetic disorders will be in one respect morally preferable to using genetic selection for the same purpose: gene editing will benefit particular future persons, while genetic selection would merely replace them. We first construct the most plausible defence of this suggestion—the benefit argument—and defend it against a possible objection. We then advance another objection: the benefit argument succeeds only when restricted to cases in which the gene-edited child would have been brought into existence even if gene editing had not been employed. Our argument relies on a standard account of comparative benefit which has recently been criticised on the grounds that it succumbs to the so-called ‘pre-emption problem’. We end by considering how our argument would be affected were the standard account revised in an attempt to evade this problem. We consider three revised accounts and argue that, on all three, our critique of the benefit argument stands.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The authors developed an ontology for classical particle mechanics that provides a precise instance of symmetry fundamentalism, the view that symmetries are fundamental aspects of physical reality and these aspects are more fundamental than what one might ordinarily think of as the fundamental building blocks of the world, such as elementary particles.
Abstract: Physicists have suggested what I call symmetry fundamentalism: the view that symmetries are fundamental aspects of physical reality and that these aspects are more fundamental than what one might ordinarily think of as the fundamental building blocks of the world, such as elementary particles. The goal of this paper is to develop an ontology for classical particle mechanics that provides a precise instance of symmetry fundamentalism.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: An examination of right action in care ethics is examined, offering reasons for care ethicists not to oppose the development of a care ethical theory thereof, and some potential formulations of a first premise of a theory ofright action are considered, demonstrating the diversity of possible first premises and arguing for a monistic subset of these.
Abstract: One of the most striking and underexplored points of difference between care ethics and other normative theories is its reluctance to offer a theory of right action. Unlike other normative ethical frameworks, care ethicists typically either neglect right action or explicitly refuse to provide a theory thereof. This paper disputes that stance. It begins with an examination of right action in care ethics, offering reasons for care ethicists not to oppose the development of a care ethical theory thereof. It then considers some potential formulations of a first premise of a theory of right action, both demonstrating the diversity of possible first premises and arguing for a monistic subset of these. It subsequently presents some potential second premises, arguing that a care ethical theory of right action ought to adopt a eudaimonistic approach to care. The paper thereby makes several inroads into a care ethical account of moral evaluation.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This article argued that no aspect of the rational assessment of emotion directly supports the claim that emotions represent evaluative properties, and they showed how this inference can be matured into an inference from fittingness to content saved.
Abstract: Many philosophers of emotion, whether perceptual or cognitive theorists, have claimed that emotions represent evaluative properties. This is often supported by an appeal to the fittingness of emotion: that emotions can be fitting shows they represent evaluative properties. In this paper, however, I argue that this inference is much too fast. In fact, no aspect of the rational assessment of emotion directly supports the claim that emotions represent evaluative properties. This inference can, however, be matured into an inference to the best explanation. But this requires coming to terms with a significant emerging rival, the attitudinal theory of emotion. In this paper, I show how this can be accomplished and the inference from fittingness to content saved.


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: This paper argued that Ayer's criterion of meaning can be defended from classical proofs of its triviality by the adoption of a relevant logic, an idea which is motivated because, according to Ayer, the genuinely factual statements are those which observation is.
Abstract: A. J. Ayer’s empiricist criterion of meaning was supposed to have sorted all statements into nonsense on the one hand, and tautologies or genuinely factual statements on the other. Unfortunately for Ayer, it follows from classical logic that his criterion is trivial – it classifies all statements as either tautologies or genuinely factual, but none as nonsense. However, in this paper I argue that Ayer’s criterion of meaning can be defended from classical proofs of its triviality by the adoption of a relevant logic – an idea which is motivated because, according to Ayer, the genuinely factual statements are those which observation is


Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors argue that there is no philosophically useful good-for or well-being concept that's neither merely descriptive in the sense of naturalistic nor reducible to "simply good".
Abstract: This paper challenges the widely held view that ‘good for’, ‘well-being’, and related terms express a distinctive evaluative concept of central importance for ethics and separate from ‘simply good’ as used by G. E. Moore and others. More specifically, it argues that there's no philosophically useful good-for or well-being concept that's neither merely descriptive in the sense of naturalistic nor reducible to ‘simply good’. The paper distinguishes two interpretations of the common claim that the value ‘good for’ expresses is distinctively ‘subject-relative’. One concerns the ground of this value, or the properties that make something good for you; it says these must involve some relation to you. The other concerns the resulting value itself, or what supervenes on this ground; it says that too involves a relation. Neither interpretation, the paper argues, yields a significantly distinct evaluative concept. The ethically fundamental evaluative concept is just ‘simply good’.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this article, the authors argue that creationism based on referentialism has enough resources to individuate fictional objects and hence can address the alleged identity problems: every alleged problematic case regarding the identity of fictional objects is well explained in terms of the notions of authorial intention, gappy proposition, inadvertent creation, and reference shift.
Abstract: This paper deals with the identity problems of fictional objects, focusing on Anthony Everett's and Stuart Brock's leading criticisms against fictional creationism, the view that fictional objects are abstract objects created by our acts involving literary practices. My primary aim is to argue that creationism based on referentialism has enough resources to individuate fictional objects and hence can address the alleged identity problems: every alleged problematic case regarding the identity of fictional objects is well explained in terms of the notions of authorial intention, gappy proposition, inadvertent creation, and reference shift.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: According to the recent Perceptual Confidence view, perceptual experiences possess not only a representational content, but also a degree of confidence in that content as discussed by the authors, and the motivations for this view are partly phenomenological and partly epistemic.
Abstract: According to the recent Perceptual Confidence view, perceptual experiences possess not only a representational content, but also a degree of confidence in that content. The motivations for this view are partly phenomenological and partly epistemic. We discuss both the phenomenological and epistemic motivations for the view, and the resulting account of the interface between perceptual experiences and degrees of belief. We conclude that, in their present state of development, orthodox accounts of perceptual experience are still to be favoured over the perceptual confidence view.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: In this paper, a framework for understanding agnosticism is provided, which accounts for the various agnostic stances and the plurality of agnostics. But it does not explicitly define agnostic attitudes.
Abstract: We provide a framework for understanding agnosticism. The framework accounts for the varieties of agnosticism while vindicating the unity of the phenomenon. This combination of unity and plurality is achieved by taking the varieties of agnosticism to be represented by several agnostic stances, all of which share a common core provided by what we call the minimal agnostic attitude. We illustrate the fruitfulness of the framework by showing how it can be applied to several philosophical debates. In particular, several philosophical positions can be aptly conceived of as instances of agnosticism whilst retaining their differences and distinguishing features.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The relationship between music and dance can sometimes be a match, a remarkable fit between the audible manifestation that music is and the visual or kinaesthetic manifestation that dance is.
Abstract: The relationship between music and dance can sometimes be a ‘match’, a remarkable fit between the audible manifestation that music is and the visual or kinaesthetic manifestation that dance is. A match between two things seems to require a common measure with respect to which the match obtains. What can this be for two so different phenomena as music and dance? I argue that the most promising answer is: movement. This answer will not be satisfactory unless the movement of music and the movement of dance are the same on some level. I suggest that they are: there are qualities of movement that guide both dancers and musicians when producing dance and music as perceptible phenomena. But the match in qualities is elusive, since the qualities are instantiated in different ways in music and dance, respectively.

Journal ArticleDOI
TL;DR: The authors argued that shame is a reactive attitude in the sense that it does not concern moral accountability, a view recently defended by Andreas Carlsson and Douglas Portmore, and also supported by others.
Abstract: It is widely agreed that reactive attitudes play a central role in our practices concerned with holding people responsible. However, it remains controversial which emotional attitudes count as reactive attitudes such that they are eligible for this central role. Specifically, though theorists near universally agree that guilt is a reactive attitude, they are much more hesitant on whether to also include shame. This paper presents novel arguments for the view that shame is a reactive attitude. The arguments also support the view that shame is a reactive attitude in the sense that concerns moral accountability. The discussion thereby challenges both the view that shame is not a reactive attitude at all, suggested by philosophers such as R. Jay Wallace and Stephen Darwall, and the view that shame is a reactive attitude but does not concern moral accountability, recently defended by Andreas Carlsson and Douglas Portmore.