scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessJournal ArticleDOI

Embedding Irony, and the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction

TLDR
The authors argue that we need to re-think the semantics/pragmatics distinction in the light of new evidence from embedding of irony and raise a new version of the old problem of "embedded impli...
Abstract
This paper argues that we need to re-think the semantics/pragmatics distinction in the light of new evidence from embedding of irony. This raises a new version of the old problem of ‘embedded impli...

read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

University of Birmingham
Embedding Irony, and the Semantics/Pragmatics
Distinction
Popa-Wyatt, Mihaela
DOI:
10.1080/0020174X.2018.1446048
License:
None: All rights reserved
Document Version
Peer reviewed version
Citation for published version (Harvard):
Popa-Wyatt, M 2018, 'Embedding Irony, and the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction', Inquiry.
https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2018.1446048
Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal
Publisher Rights Statement:
This is an Accepted Manuscript of an article published by Taylor & Francis in Inquiry : An interdisciplinary journal of philosophy and the social
sciences on 2nd March 2018, available online: http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/0020174X.2018.1446048
General rights
Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the
copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes
permitted by law.
•Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication.
•Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private
study or non-commercial research.
•User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?)
•Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain.
Where a licence is displayed above, please note the terms and conditions of the licence govern your use of this document.
When citing, please reference the published version.
Take down policy
While the University of Birmingham exercises care and attention in making items available there are rare occasions when an item has been
uploaded in error or has been deemed to be commercially or otherwise sensitive.
If you believe that this is the case for this document, please contact UBIRA@lists.bham.ac.uk providing details and we will remove access to
the work immediately and investigate.
Download date: 09. Aug. 2022

EMBEDDING IRONY
Dr#Mihaela#Popa-Wyatt#
Department#of#Philosophy#
University#of#Birmingham#
Edgbaston,#Birmingham#B15#2TT,#UK#
popa.michaela@gmail.com#
https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9239-9247!
!1

EMBEDDING IRONY
Embedding Irony
and the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction
This paper argues that we need to re-think the semantics/pragmatics distinction in the light of new
evidence from embedding of irony. This raises a new version of the old problem of embedded implicatures’.
I argue that embedded irony isn’t fully explained by solutions proposed for other embedded implicatures.
I first consider two strategies: weak pragmatics and strong pragmatics. These explain embedded irony as truth-
conditional content. However, by trying to shoehorn irony into said-content, they raise problems of their
own. I conclude by considering how a modified Gricean model can explain that irony embeds qua
implicature. This leads us to prefer a local implicature model.
Keywords: embedded irony, embedding, truth-conditional compositionality, embedded implicatures,
local implicatures, semantics/pragmatics distinction.!
!2

EMBEDDING IRONY
Embedding Irony
and the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction
This paper argues that we need to re-think the semantics/pragmatics distinction in the light of new
evidence from embedding of irony. This raises a new version of the old problem of embedded implicatures’.
I argue that embedded irony isn’t fully explained by solutions proposed for other embedded implicatures.
I first consider two strategies: weak pragmatics and strong pragmatics. These explain embedded irony as truth-
conditional content. However, by trying to shoehorn irony into said-content, they raise problems of their
own. I conclude by considering how a modified Gricean model can explain that irony embeds qua
implicature. This leads us to prefer a local implicature model.
1" The Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction
Where does semantics end and pragmatics begin? The traditional answer has been that pragmatics
starts where semantics finishes. To a first approximation, this division of labour reflects Grice’s
(1989) division of speaker-meaning into two parts: what is said and what is implicated. Saying comes
before implicating, and functions as a central part of the supporting evidence for working out what
else, or what more, the speaker may have implicated in uttering a sentence S. Most of the debates
on the semantics/pragmatics distinction have predominantly focused on the epistemological
question of how meaning is derived—how it is that hearers try to work out what it is that the
speaker meant. This is concerned with what kind of information and processes hearers use as
1
evidence to form a hypothesis about what the speaker has said and/or implicated in uttering S.
Accordingly, said-content is determined compositionally—by composing the semantic meanings or
contents of individual words (relative to context), together with their mode of composition via the
syntactic structure of the sentence. Implicated-content is inferred contextually by reasoning about why
the speaker has said what she said in a given context. These two ways of extracting meaning do not
mix: saying is bottom-up driven by rules of grammar; implicating is top-down driven by common-
sense reasoning.
Grice distinguishes the epistemological question from the metaphysical question of meaning determination. The
1
metaphysical determination concerns how meaning supervenes on the speaker’s communicative intentions. In other words,
meaning comes from the mental states of the speaker and these mental states involve higher-order type intentions to get
something across while being perceived by the hearer as trying to get something across. The epistemological determination
is concerned with how hearers recognise the speaker’s communicative intention and work out what it is that they are trying
to communicate. Though the metaphysical and epistemological questions are separate, they constrain one another. Speakers
want (and expect) to be understood, and hearers seek (and expect) to understand. So, in forming communicative intentions
the speaker relies on the hearer’s ability to grasp those intentions. Vice-versa, in interpreting an utterance, the hearer relies
in turn on the speaker’s capacity to exploit this ability. For details about the methodological flaws that may arise from
conflating this distinction, see Bach (2005a), Neale (2005), among others.
!3

EMBEDDING IRONY
This way of motivating the semantics/pragmatics distinction has been fraught with heated
disputes because it doesn’t perfectly align with the said/implicated distinction. This is because we
2
often leave things un-said in what we say. So some pragmatics is needed to determine what was said,
either to fill in what is missing, or fill out what is not contextually specific. This much is undisputed.
What is disputed is how much contextual supplementation is needed, and what kind of pragmatic
processes should be allowed to provide it. Some propose weak pragmatics; others strong pragmatics.
Proponents of weak pragmatics require that the pragmatic supplementation be constrained by
semantic rules (e.g. saturation of indexicals, demonstratives, and other context-sensitive expressions,
disambiguation). This results in ‘weak pragmatic effects which feed directly into compositionality—
3
thus retaining a strong and robust semantic compositionality. Proponents of strong pragmatics are more
liberal, allowing linguistically unconstrained pragmatic processes to intrude into what is said. This
4
sometimes serves to fill the gap between sentence meaning and what we say, and other times it may
require recruiting certain types of implicatures in order to fill in the gap between what we say and
what we mean, when what we mean goes well beyond what the words themselves mean. This
requires a ‘free’ pragmatic inference—‘free’ in the sense of a top-down reasoning unconstrained by
linguistic rules. This reasoning is similar to calculating implicatures, except that it applies locally to
individual words and phrases. This results in strong pragmatic effects which feed directly into
compositionality—though this calls for a weaker compositionality known as pragmatic compositionality.
Despite the differences in details, both camps are equally motivated by a desire to preserve
compositionality—more specifically, truth-conditional compositionality which holds that both inputs and
outputs of compositional processes are truth-conditional contents. One way to secure this is to ban
implicatures from intruding into compositionality. This thesis has taken various guises —here I shall
5
call it truth-conditional embedding (henceforth TC-Embedding):
TC-Embedding:" If S is embedded in a compound sentence, like conditionals, disjunctions,
" " belief-reports, etc., then what S contributes to the compound cannot be an !
!!implicature, but only a truth-conditional content.
TC-Embedding is associated with a commonly held assumption that logical operators work truth-
functionally, by mapping S’s truth-conditions onto the truth-conditions of the whole compound.
6
This means that S embedded under an operator is only performed in a propositional act—an act of
uttering a sentence with a propositional (true/false assessable) content such that the utterance can
I’ll use the said/implicated distinction as a proxy for the semantics/pragmatics distinction, though an imperfect one. As
2
we’ll see, pragmatics intrudes into semantics in order to fill the gap between the sentence meaning and what the speaker
means to say. Nevertheless, the kind of pragmatics that contrasts sharply with semantics concerns paradigmatic
conversational implicatures. For simplicity, I leave aside controversial questions of whether conventional implicatures exist
(for a denial, see Bach 1994), or whether conversational implicatures exist (for a denial, see Gauker 2001, Lepore & Stone
2014), or whether or not we can have a semantics for a language (for a denial, see Travis 2000; Pietroski forth).
Stanley (2000), Stanley & Szabó (2000), King & Stanley (2005), Cappelan & Lepore (2005), Borg (2004), among others.
3
Recanati (2004), Carston (2002), Bezuidenhout (2002), among others.
4
This thesis usually goes by the name of Scope Principle, cf. Recanati (1989); see also Wilson (1975), Carston (1991), Green
5
(1998), O’Rourke (2003), Camp (2012).
For Grice, the semantics of connectives is given entirely by their standard truth-functional interpretation, which is non-
6
cancellable content.
!4

Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI

Irony and Sarcasm in Ethical Perspective

Abstract: Abstract Irony and sarcasm are two quite different, sometimes morally dubious, linguistic tropes. We can draw a distinction between them if we identify irony as a speech act that calls what is bad good and, correspondingly, sarcasm calls good bad. This allows us to ask, which one is morally worse. My argument is based on the idea that the speaker can legitimately bypass what is good and call it bad, which is to say that she may literally mean what she says. This is not true of the opposite case: one cannot bypass what is bad and, therefore, she paradoxically does not mean what she says. In other words, irony is a morally less guilty trope. What is bad has its faults and thus it can be ironized; what is good is without blemish and thus it is difficult to know how it could be called bad. Also, irony can be freely intended, or verbal, or it can be situational in social context. I also discuss dramatic irony in Classical context. Sarcasm does not allow such complexity. Instead, we speak of cynicism and even nihilism as moral attitudes that accompany sarcasm and give it its typical force; or sarcasm may lead to cynicism and nihilism, that is, to the denial of values. Irony does not entail any corresponding attitudes or moral positions. This paper is a philosophical contribution to the ethics of communication and language.
MonographDOI

The Manipulative Disguise of Truth: Tricks and threats of implicit communication

TL;DR: In this article, a guide to the most dangerous traps of deceptive language as triggered by implicit communication strategies such as presupposition, implicature, topicalization and vague expressions is presented.
Journal ArticleDOI

Compound Figures: A Multi-Channel View of Communication and Psychological Plausibility

TL;DR: In this paper, the author argues that irony is logically dependent on metaphorical content, but makes no claim about how psychologically plausible this is in terms of the processing order, and proposes a more psychologically plausible account of communicative acts and intentions.
Journal ArticleDOI

Mimetic Evil: A Conceptual and Ethical Study

TL;DR: In this paper, the authors provide a systematic framework for understanding mimetic mocking in terms of emulation and simulation, and introduce an idea of universal mimesis and discuss Rene Girard's theory of desire.
References
More filters
Book

Studies in the Way of Words

TL;DR: This volume, Grice's first hook, includes the long-delayed publication of his enormously influential 1967 William James Lectures as mentioned in this paper, which is a vital book for all who are interested in Anglo-American philosophy.
Book

Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of Generalized Conversational Implicature

TL;DR: In this article, the author outlines a theory of presumptive meanings, or preferred interpretations, governing the use of language, building on the idea of implicature developed by the philosopher H. P. Grice.
BookDOI

Thoughts and Utterances

Robyn Carston
Journal ArticleDOI

Context and logical form

TL;DR: The authors argue that alleffects of extra-linguistic context on the truth-conditions of an assertion are traceable to elements in the actual syntactic structure of the sentence uttered.
Journal ArticleDOI

On Quantifier Domain Restriction

TL;DR: This paper provides a comprehensive survey of the space of possible analyses of the phenomenon of quantifier domain restriction, together with a set of considerations which militate against all but the own proposal.