scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessJournal ArticleDOI

Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox: From concepts to applications

Reads0
Chats0
TLDR
In this article, the authors examined the field of the EPR gedanken experiment, from the original paper of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, through to modern theoretical proposals of how to realize both the continuous-variable and discrete versions of EPR paradox.
Abstract
This Colloquium examines the field of the Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (EPR) gedanken experiment, from the original paper of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, through to modern theoretical proposals of how to realize both the continuous-variable and discrete versions of the EPR paradox. The relationship with entanglement and Bell's theorem are analyzed, and the progress to date towards experimental confirmation of the EPR paradox is summarized, with a detailed treatment of the continuous-variable paradox in laser-based experiments. Practical techniques covered include continuous-wave parametric amplifier and optical fiber quantum soliton experiments. Current proposals for extending EPR experiments to massive-particle systems are discussed, including spin squeezing, atomic position entanglement, and quadrature entanglement in ultracold atoms. Finally, applications of this technology to quantum key distribution, quantum teleportation, and entanglement swapping are examined.

read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox:
From concepts to applications
M. D. Reid and P. D. Drummond
ARC Centre of Excellence for Quantum-Atom Optics and Centre for Atom Optics and
Ultrafast Spectroscopy, Swinburne University of Technology, P.O. Box 218, Melbourne,
Victoria 3122 Australia
W. P. Bowen
School of Physical Sciences, University of Queensland, Brisbane, Queensland 4072,
Australia
E. G. Cavalcanti
Centre for Quantum Dynamics, Griffith University, Brisbane, Queensland 4111, Australia
P. K. Lam and H. A. Bachor
ARC Centre of Excellence for Quantum-Atom Optics, Building 38, The Australian National
University, Canberra, Australian Capital Territory 0200, Australia
U. L. Andersen
Department of Physics, Technical University of Denmark, Building 309, 2800 Lyngby,
Denmark
G. Leuchs
Max-Planck Institute for the Science of Light and Department of Physics, Universität
Erlangen-Nürnberg, D-91058 Erlangen, Germany
Published 10 December 2009
This Colloquium examines the field of the Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen EPR gedanken
experiment, from the original paper of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, through to modern theoretical
proposals of how to realize both the continuous-variable and discrete versions of the EPR paradox.
The relationship with entanglement and Bell’s theorem are analyzed, and the progress to date towards
experimental confirmation of the EPR paradox is summarized, with a detailed treatment of the
continuous-variable paradox in laser-based experiments. Practical techniques covered include
continuous-wave parametric amplifier and optical fiber quantum soliton experiments. Current
proposals for extending EPR experiments to massive-particle systems are discussed, including spin
squeezing, atomic position entanglement, and quadrature entanglement in ultracold atoms. Finally,
applications of this technology to quantum key distribution, quantum teleportation, and entanglement
swapping are examined.
DOI: 10.1103/RevModPhys.81.1727 PACS numbers: 03.65.Ud, 03.67.Bg, 03.75.Gg, 42.50.Xa
CONTENTS
I. Introduction 1728
II. The Continuous Variable EPR Paradox 1729
A. The 1935 argument: EPR’s elements of reality 1729
B. Schrödinger’s response: entanglement and
separability 1730
III. Discrete Spin Variables and Bell’s Theorem 1731
A. The EPR-Bohm paradox: Early EPR experiments 1731
B. Bell’s theorem 1731
C. Experimental tests of Bell’s theorem 1732
IV. EPR Argument for Real Particles and Fields 1732
A. Inferred Heisenberg inequality: Continuous variable
case 1732
B. Criteria for the discrete EPR paradox 1734
C. A practical linear-estimate criterion for EPR 1734
D. Experimental criteria for demonstrating the paradox 1735
V. Theoretical Model for a Continuous Variable EPR
Experiment 1735
A. Two-mode squeezed states 1735
B. Measurement techniques 1736
C. Effects of loss and imperfect detectors 1737
VI. EPR, Entanglement, and Bell Criteria 1738
A. Steering 1738
B. Symmetric EPR paradox 1738
C. EPR as a special type of entanglement 1738
D. EPR and Bell’s nonlocality 1739
VII. Continuous-Wave EPR Experiments 1740
A. Parametric oscillator experiments 1740
B. Experimental results 1741
VIII. Pulsed EPR Experiments 1742
A. Optical fiber experiment 1742
B. Parametric amplifier experiment 1743
REVIEWS OF MODERN PHYSICS, VOLUME 81, OCTOBER–DECEMBER 2009
0034-6861/2009/814/172725 ©2009 The American Physical Society1727

IX. Spin EPR and Atoms 1744
A. Transfer of optical entanglement to atomic
ensembles 1744
B. Conditional atom ensemble entanglement 1745
X. Application of EPR Entanglement 1745
A. Entanglement-based quantum key distribution 1745
B. Quantum teleportation and entanglement swapping 1746
XI. Outlook 1747
Acknowledgments 1748
References 1748
I. INTRODUCTION
In 1935, Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen EPR origi-
nated the famous “EPR paradox” Einstein et al., 1935.
This argument concerns two spatially separated particles
which have both perfectly correlated positions and mo-
menta, as is predicted possible by quantum mechanics.
The EPR paper spurred investigations into the nonlocal-
ity of quantum mechanics, leading to a direct challenge
of the philosophies taken for granted by most physicists.
Furthermore, the EPR paradox brought into sharp focus
the concept of entanglement, now considered to be the
underpinning of quantum technology.
Despite its large significance, relatively little has been
done to directly realize the original EPR gedanken ex-
periment. Most published discussion has centred around
the testing of theorems by Bell 1964, whose work was
derived from that of EPR, but proposed more stringent
tests dealing with a different set of measurements. The
purpose of this Colloquium is to give a different per-
spective. We go back to EPR’s original paper, and ana-
lyze the current theoretical and experimental status and
implications of the EPR paradox itself, as an indepen-
dent body of work.
A paradox is “a seemingly absurd or self-
contradictory statement or proposition that may in fact
be true.”
1
The EPR conclusion was based on the as-
sumption of local realism, and thus the EPR argument
pinpoints a contradiction between local realism and the
completeness of quantum mechanics. The argument was
therefore termed a “paradox” by Schrödinger 1935b,
Bohm 1951, Bohm and Aharonov 1957, and Bell
1964. EPR took the prevailing view of their era that
local realism must be valid. They argued from this
premise that quantum mechanics must be incomplete.
With the insight later provided by Bell 1964, the EPR
argument is best viewed as the first demonstration of
problems arising from the premise of local realism.
The intention of EPR was to motivate the search for a
theory “better” than quantum mechanics. However,
EPR never questioned the correctness of quantum me-
chanics, only its completeness. They showed that if a set
of assumptions, which we now call local realism, is up-
held, then quantum mechanics must be incomplete. Ow-
ing to the subsequent work of Bell, we now know what
EPR did not know: local realism, the “realistic philoso-
phy of most working scientists” Clauser and Shimony,
1978, is itself in question. Thus, an experimental real-
ization of the EPR proposal provides a way to demon-
strate a type of entanglement inextricably connected
with quantum nonlocality.
In the sense that the local realistic theory envisaged
by them cannot exist, EPR were “wrong.” What EPR
did reveal in their paper, however, was an inconsistency
between local realism and the completeness of quantum
mechanics. Hence, we must abandon at least one of
these premises. Their analysis was clever, insightful, and
correct. The EPR paper therefore provides a way to dis-
tinguish quantum mechanics as a complete theory from
classical reality, in a quantitative sense.
The conclusions of the EPR argument can only be
drawn if certain correlations between the positions and
momenta of the particles can be confirmed experimen-
tally. The work of EPR, like that of Bell, requires experi-
mental demonstration, since it could be supposed that
the quantum states in question are not physically acces-
sible, or that quantum mechanics itself is wrong. It is not
feasible to prepare the perfect correlations of the origi-
nal EPR proposal. Instead, we show that the violation of
an inferred Heisenberg uncertainty principle—an “EPR
inequality”—is eminently practical. These EPR in-
equalities provide a way to test the incompatibility of
local realism, as generalized to a nondeterministic situa-
tion, with the completeness of quantum mechanics. Vio-
lating an EPR inequality is a demonstration of the EPR
paradox.
In a nutshell, EPR experiments provide an important
complement to those proposed by Bell. While the con-
clusions of Bell’s theorem are stronger, the EPR ap-
proach is applicable to a greater variety of physical sys-
tems. Most Bell tests have been confined to single
photon counting measurements with discrete outcomes,
whereas recent EPR experiments have involved con-
tinuous variable outcomes and high detection efficien-
cies. This leads to possibilities for tests of quantum non-
locality in new regimes involving massive particles and
macroscopic systems. Significantly, new applications in
the field of quantum information are feasible.
In this Colloquium, we outline the theory of EPR’s
seminal paper, and also provide an overview of more
recent theoretical and experimental achievements. We
discuss the development of the EPR inequalities, and
how they can be applied to quantify the EPR paradox
for both spin and amplitude measurements. A limiting
factor for the early spin EPR experiments of Wu and
Shaknov 1950, Freedman and Clauser 1972, Aspect,
Grangier, and Roger 1981, and others was the low de-
tection efficiencies, which meant probabilities were sur-
mised using a postselected ensemble of counts. In con-
trast, the more recent EPR experiments report an
amplitude correlation measured over the whole en-
semble, to produce unconditionally, on demand, states
that give the entanglement of the EPR paradox. How-
ever, causal separation has not yet been achieved. We
explain the methodology and development of these ex-
1
Compact Oxford English Dictionary, 2006,
www.askoxford.com
1728
Reid et al.: Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen
Rev. Mod. Phys., Vol. 81, No. 4, October–December 2009

periments, first performed by Ou, Pereira, Kimble, and
Peng 1992.
An experimental realization of the EPR proposal will
always imply entanglement, and we analyze the relation-
ship between entanglement, the EPR paradox, and
Bell’s theorem. In looking to the future, we review re-
cent experiments and proposals involving massive par-
ticles, ranging from room-temperature spin-squeezing
experiments to proposals for the EPR-entanglement of
quadratures of ultracold Bose-Einstein condensates. A
number of possible applications of these EPR experi-
ments have already been proposed, for example, in the
areas of quantum cryptography and quantum teleporta-
tion. Finally, we discuss these, with emphasis on those
applications that use the form of entanglement closely
associated with the EPR paradox.
II. THE CONTINUOUS VARIABLE EPR PARADOX
Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen 1935 focused atten-
tion on the nonlocality of quantum mechanics by consid-
ering the case of two spatially separated quantum par-
ticles that have both maximally correlated momenta and
maximally anticorrelated positions. In their paper en-
titled Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physi-
cal Reality Be Considered Complete?,” they pointed out
an apparent inconsistency between such states and the
premise of local realism, arguing that this inconsistency
could only be resolved through a completion of quan-
tum mechanics. Presumably EPR had in mind to supple-
ment quantum theory with a hidden variable theory,
consistent with the “elements of reality” defined in their
paper.
After Bohm 1952 demonstrated that a nonlocal
hidden variable theory was feasible, subsequent work by
Bell 1964 proved the impossibility of completing quan-
tum mechanics with local hidden variable theories. This
resolves the paradox by pointing to a failure of local
realism itself—at least at the microscopic level. The
EPR argument nevertheless remains significant. It re-
veals the necessity of either rejecting local realism or
completing quantum mechanics or both.
A. The 1935 argument: EPR’s elements of reality
The EPR argument is based on the premises that are
now generally referred to as local realism quotes are
from the original paper:
“If, without disturbing a system, we can predict with
certainty the value of a physical quantity,” then
“there exists an element of physical reality corre-
sponding to this physical quantity.” The element of
reality represents the predetermined value for the
physical quantity.
The locality assumption postulates no action at a dis-
tance, so that measurements at a location B cannot
immediately “disturb” the system at a spatially sepa-
rated location A.
EPR treated the case of a nonfactorizable pure state
, which describes the results for measurements per-
formed on two spatially separated systems at A and B
Fig. 1. “Nonfactorizable” means entangled, that is, we
cannot express
as a simple product
=
A
B
,
where
A
and
B
are quantum states for the results of
measurements at A and B, respectively.
In the first part of their paper, EPR pointed out in a
general way the puzzling aspects of such entangled
states. The key issue is that one can expand
in terms
of more than one basis, which correspond to different
experimental settings, parametrized by
. Consider the
state
=
dx
x
,A
u
x
,B
. 1
Here the eigenvalue x could be continuous or discrete.
The parameter setting
at the detector B is used to
define a particular orthogonal measurement basis
u
x
,B
. On measurement at B, this projects out a wave
function
x
,A
at A, the process called “reduction of
the wave packet.” The puzzling issue is that different
choices of measurements
at B will cause reduction of
the wave packet at A in more than one possible way.
EPR state that, “as a consequence of two different mea-
surements” at B, the “second system may be left in
states with two different wave functions.” Yet, “no real
change can take place in the second system in conse-
quence of anything that may be done to the first sys-
tem.” Schrödinger 1935b, 1936 studied this case as
well, referring to the apparent influence by B on the
remote system A as “steering.” Despite the apparently
acausal nature of state collapse Herbert, 1982, the lin-
earity or “no-cloning” property of quantum mechanics
rules out superluminal communication Dieks, 1982;
Wootters and Zurek, 1982.
The problem was crystallized by EPR with a specific
example, shown in Fig. 1. EPR considered two spatially
separated subsystems, at A and B, each with two observ-
ables x
ˆ
and p
ˆ
where x
ˆ
and p
ˆ
are noncommuting quan-
tum operators, with commutator x
ˆ
,p
ˆ
=x
ˆ
p
ˆ
p
ˆ
x
ˆ
=2C0.
The results of the measurements x
ˆ
and p
ˆ
are denoted x
and p, respectively, and we follow this convention
throughout the paper. We note that EPR assumed a con-
tinuous variable spectrum, but this is not crucial to the
concepts they raised. In our treatment we scale the ob-
servables so that C = i, for simplicity, which gives rise to
the Heisenberg uncertainty relation
FIG. 1. Color online The original EPR gedanken experi-
ment. Two particles move from a source S into spatially sepa-
rated regions A and B, and yet continue to have maximally
correlated positions and anticorrelated momenta. This means
one may make an instant prediction, with 100% accuracy, of
either the position or momentum of particle A by performing a
measurement at B.
1729
Reid et al.: Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen
Rev. Mod. Phys., Vol. 81, No. 4, October–December 2009

xp 1, 2
where x and p are the standard deviations in the re-
sults x and p, respectively.
EPR considered the quantum wave function
defined
in a position representation
x,x
B
=
e
ip/兲共xx
B
x
0
dp, 3
where x
0
is a constant implying spacelike separation.
Here the pairs x and p refer to the results for position
and momentum measurements at A, while x
B
and p
B
refer to position and momentum at B. We leave off the
superscript for system A, to emphasize the inherent
asymmetry that exists in the EPR argument, where one
system A is “steered” by the other B.
According to quantum mechanics, one can “predict
with certainty” that a measurement x
ˆ
will give result
x
B
+x
0
, if a measurement x
ˆ
B
, with result x
B
, was already
performed at B. One may also predict with certainty the
result of measurement p
ˆ
, for a different choice of mea-
surement at B. If the momentum at B is measured to be
p, then the result for p
ˆ
is p. These predictions are made
“without disturbing the second system” at A, based on
the assumption, implicit in the original EPR paper, of
“locality.” The locality assumption can be strengthened
if the measurement events at A and B are causally sepa-
rated such that no signal can travel from one event to
the other, unless faster than the speed of light.
The remainder of the EPR argument may be summa-
rized as follows Clauser and Shimony, 1978. Assuming
local realism, one deduces that both the measurement
outcomes, for x and p at A, are predetermined. The per-
fect correlation of x with x
B
+x
0
implies the existence of
an element of reality for the measurement x
ˆ
. Similarly,
the correlation of p with p
B
implies an element of re-
ality for p
ˆ
. Although not mentioned by EPR, it will
prove useful to mathematically represent the elements
of reality for x
ˆ
and p
ˆ
by the respective variables
x
A
and
p
A
, whose “possible values are the predicted results of
the measurement” Mermin, 1990.
To continue the argument, local realism implies the
existence of two elements of reality,
x
A
and
p
A
, that
simultaneously predetermine, with absolute definiteness,
the results for either measurement x or p at A. These
elements of reality for the localized subsystem A are not
themselves consistent with quantum mechanics. Simulta-
neous determinacy for both the position and momentum
is not possible for any quantum state. Hence, assuming
the validity of local realism, one concludes quantum me-
chanics to be incomplete. Bohr’s early reply Bohr, 1935
to EPR was essentially a defense of quantum mechanics
and a questioning of the relevance of local realism.
B. Schrödinger’s response: entanglement and separability
It was soon realized that the paradox was intimately
related to the structure of the wavefunction in quantum
mechanics, and the opposite ideas of entanglement and
separability. Schrödinger 1935a pointed out that the
EPR two-particle wave function in Eq. 3 was
verschränkten—which he later translated as entangled
Schrödinger, 1935b—i.e., not of the separable form
A
B
. Both he and Furry 1936 considered as a possible
resolution of the paradox that this entanglement de-
grades as the particles separate spatially, so that EPR
correlations would not be physically realizable. Experi-
ments considered in this Colloquium show this reso-
lution to be untenable microscopically, but the proposal
led to later theories which only modify quantum me-
chanics macroscopically Ghirardi et al., 1986; Bell, 1988;
Bassi and Ghirardi, 2003.
Quantum inseparability entanglement for a general
mixed quantum state is defined as the failure of
ˆ
=
dP
ˆ
A
ˆ
B
, 4
where dP= 1 and
ˆ
is the density operator.
2
Here
is a discrete or continuous label for component states,
and
ˆ
A,B
correspond to density operators that are re-
stricted to the Hilbert spaces A, B respectively.
The definition of inseparability extends beyond that of
the EPR situation, in that one considers a whole spec-
trum of measurement choices, parametrized by
for
those performed on system A, and by
for those per-
formed on B. We introduce the new notation x
ˆ
A
and
x
ˆ
B
to describe all measurements at A and B. Denoting
the eigenstates of x
ˆ
A
by x
A
, we define P
Q
x
A
,
=x
A
ˆ
A
x
A
and P
Q
x
B
,= x
B
ˆ
B
x
B
, which are the
localized probabilities for observing results x
A
and x
B
,
respectively. The separability condition 4 then implies
that joint probabilities Px
A
,x
B
are given as
Px
A
,x
B
=
dPP
Q
x
A
P
Q
x
B
. 5
We note the restriction that, for example,
2
x
A
2
p
A
1, where
2
x
A
and
2
p
A
are
the variances of P
Q
x
A
, for the choices
corre-
sponding to position x
A
and momentum p
A
, respectively.
The original EPR state of Eq. 3 is not separable.
The most precise signatures of entanglement rely on
entropic or more general information-theoretic mea-
sures. This can be seen in its simplest form when
ˆ
is a
pure state so that Tr
ˆ
2
=1. Under these conditions, it
follows that
ˆ
is entangled if and only if the von Neu-
mann entropy measure of either reduced density matrix
ˆ
A
=Tr
B
ˆ
or
ˆ
B
=Tr
A
ˆ
is positive. Here the entropy is
defined as
2
Here we use entanglement in the simplest sense to mean a
state for a composite system which is nonseparable, so that Eq.
4 fails. The issues of the EPR paradox that make entangle-
ment interesting demand that the systems A and B can be
spatially separated, and these are the types of systems ad-
dressed here. The relation, between a quantum correlation and
entanglement, is discussed by Shore 2008.
1730
Reid et al.: Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen
Rev. Mod. Phys., Vol. 81, No. 4, October–December 2009

S
ˆ
=−Tr
ˆ
ln
ˆ
. 6
When
ˆ
is a mixed state, one must turn to variational
measures like the entanglement of formation to obtain
necessary and sufficient conditions Bennett et al., 1996.
The entanglement of formation leads to the popular
concurrence measure for two qubits Wootters, 1998.A
necessary but not sufficient condition for entanglement
is the positive partial transpose criterion of Peres 1996.
III. DISCRETE SPIN VARIABLES AND BELL’S
THEOREM
A. The EPR-Bohm paradox: Early EPR experiments
As the continuous variable EPR proposal was not ex-
perimentally realizable at the time, much of the early
work relied on an adaptation of the EPR paradox to
spin measurements by Bohm 1951, as depicted in Fig.
2.
Specifically, Bohm considered two spatially separated
spin-1/2 particles at A and B produced in an entangled
singlet state often referred to as the EPR-Bohm state or
the Bell state,
=
1
2
1
2
A
1
2
B
1
2
A
1
2
B
. 7
Here ±
1
2
A
are eigenstates of the spin operator J
ˆ
z
A
, and
we use J
ˆ
z
A
, J
ˆ
x
A
, J
ˆ
y
A
to define the spin components mea-
sured at location A. The spin eigenstates and measure-
ments at B are defined similarly. By considering differ-
ent quantization axes, one obtains different but
equivalent expansions of
in Eq. 1, just as EPR sug-
gested.
Bohm’s reasoning is based on the existence, for Eq.
7, of a maximum anticorrelation between not only J
ˆ
z
A
and J
ˆ
z
B
, but J
ˆ
y
A
and J
ˆ
y
B
, and also J
ˆ
x
A
and J
ˆ
x
B
. An assump-
tion of local realism would lead to the conclusion that
the three spin components of particle A were simulta-
neously predetermined, with absolute definiteness. Since
no such quantum description exists, this is the situation
of an EPR paradox. A simple explanation of the
discrete-variable EPR paradox has been presented by
Mermin 1990 in relation to the three-particle
Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger correlation Greenberger
et al., 1989.
An early attempt to realize EPR-Bohm correlations
for discrete spin variables came from Bleuler and
Bradt 1948, who examined the gamma radiation emit-
ted from positron annihilation. These are spin-one par-
ticles which form an entangled singlet. Here correlations
were measured between the polarizations of emitted
photons, but with very inefficient Compton-scattering
polarizers and detectors, and no control of causal sepa-
ration. Several further experiments were performed
along similar lines Wu and Shaknov, 1950, as well as
with correlated protons Lamehi-Rachti and Mittig,
1976. While these are sometimes regarded as demon-
strating the EPR paradox Bohm and Aharonov, 1957,
the fact that they involved extremely inefficient detec-
tors, with postselection of coincidence counts, makes
this interpretation debatable.
B. Bell’s theorem
The EPR paper concludes by referring to theories
that might complete quantum mechanics: we have
left open the question of whether or not such a descrip-
tion exists. We believe, however, that such a theory is pos-
sible.” The seminal works of Bell 1964, 1988 and
Clauser et al. 1969 CHSH clarified this issue, to show
that this speculation was wrong. Bell showed that the
predictions of local hidden variable LHV theories dif-
fer from those of quantum mechanics, for the Bell state,
Eq. 7.
Bell-CHSH considered theories for two spatially sepa-
rated subsystems A and B. As with separable states,
Eqs. 4 and 5, it is assumed there exist parameters
that are shared between the subsystems and which de-
note localized—though not necessarily quantum—states
for each. Measurements can be performed on A and B,
and the measurement choice is parametrized by
and
,
respectively. Thus, for example,
may be chosen to be
either position and momentum, as in the original EPR
gedanken experiment, or an analyzer angle as in the
Bohm-EPR gedanken experiment. We denote the result
of the measurement labelled
at A as x
A
, and use simi-
lar notation for outcomes at B. The assumption of Bell’s
locality is that the probability Px
A
for x
A
depends on
and
, but is independent of
; and similarly for
Px
B
. The local hidden variable assumption of Bell
and CHSH then implies the joint probability Px
A
,x
B
to be
Px
A
,x
B
=
dPPx
A
Px
B
, 8
where P is the distribution for the . This assumption,
which we call Bell-CHSH local realism, differs from Eq.
5 for separability, in that the probabilities Px
A
and
Px
B
do not arise from localized quantum states.
From the assumption Eq. 8 of LHV theories, Bell and
CHSH derived constraints, referred to as Bell’s inequali-
ties. They showed that quantum mechanics predicts a
FIG. 2. Color online The Bohm gedanken EPR experiment.
Two spin-
1
2
particles prepared in a singlet state move from the
source into spatially separated regions A and B, and give an-
ticorrelated outcomes for J
A
and J
B
, where
is x, y,orz.
1731
Reid et al.: Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen
Rev. Mod. Phys., Vol. 81, No. 4, October–December 2009

Figures
Citations
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI

Quantum metrology with nonclassical states of atomic ensembles

TL;DR: In this article, the authors review and illustrate the theory and experiments with atomic ensembles that have demonstrated many-particle entanglement and quantum-enhanced metrology.
Journal ArticleDOI

Quantum correlations in optical angle-orbital angular momentum variables

TL;DR: This demonstration of entanglement in an angular basis establishes that angles are genuine quantum observables and can therefore be considered a resource for quantum information processing, capable of secure, high-dimension, key distribution.
Journal ArticleDOI

Experimental EPR-steering using Bell-local states

TL;DR: In this article, it was shown that entanglement is necessary for steering, but steering can be achieved, as has now been demonstrated experimentally, with states that cannot violate a Bell inequality and therefore non-locality.
MonographDOI

Introduction to Quantum Optics: From the Semi-classical Approach to Quantized Light

TL;DR: In this paper, the authors present an excellent introduction for advanced undergraduate and beginning graduate students, familiarizing readers with the basic concepts and formalism as well as the most recent advances in quantum optics.
Journal ArticleDOI

Quantum Steering.

TL;DR: The theory of quantum steering is reviewed in this article, where the basic concepts of steering and local hidden state models are presented and their relation to entanglement and Bell nonlocality is explained.
References
More filters
Journal Article

A pulsed source of continuous variable polarization entanglement : Special issue on quantum optics and quantum entanglement

TL;DR: In this paper, the polarization entanglement was demonstrated using continuous variables in an ultra-short pulsed laser system at the telecommunications wavelength of 1.5 μm, exploiting the Kerr non-linearity of a glass fibre.
Journal ArticleDOI

Uncertainty relations for the realisation of macroscopic quantum superpositions and EPR paradoxes

TL;DR: In this article, a unified approach based on the use of quantum uncertainty relations is presented for arriving at criteria for the demonstration of the EPR paradox and macroscopic superpositions.
Journal ArticleDOI

Experimental investigation of the intensity fluctuation joint probability and conditional distributions of the twin-beam quantum state

TL;DR: The intensity fluctuation joint probability of the twin-beam quantum state, which was generated with an optical parametric oscillator operating above threshold, is given and what to the authors' knowledge is the first measurement of theintensity fluctuation conditional probability distributions of twin beams is measured.
Journal ArticleDOI

A pulsed source of continuous variable polarization entanglement

TL;DR: In this paper, the polarization entanglement was demonstrated using continuous variables in an ultra-short pulsed laser system at the telecommunications wavelength of 1.5µm using a 50:50 beamplitter.
Journal ArticleDOI

Quantum images in nonlinear optics

TL;DR: In this paper, the concept of quantum image was introduced in the context of degenerate parametric oscillators and the authors showed the gradual transformation of a quantum image into a classical image as the threshold region is scanned.
Related Papers (5)
Frequently Asked Questions (17)
Q1. What have the authors contributed in "Colloquium: the einstein-podolsky-rosen paradox: from concepts to applications" ?

This Colloquium examines the field of the Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen EPR gedanken experiment, from the original paper of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, through to modern theoretical proposals of how to realize both the continuous-variable and discrete versions of the EPR paradox. Current proposals for extending EPR experiments to massive-particle systems are discussed, including spin squeezing, atomic position entanglement, and quadrature entanglement in ultracold atoms. Finally, applications of this technology to quantum key distribution, quantum teleportation, and entanglement swapping are examined. 

In these steady-state continuous-wave experiments, however, the squeezing parameter r is time independent, and given by the inputoutput parametric gain G, such that G=e2r. 

Due to the high peak powers of the frequency doubled pulses as well as the particular choice of a highly nonlinear optical material KNBO3 , the use of a cavity was circumvented despite the fact that a very thin 100 m crystal was employed. 

Using fieldquadrature measurements and multiparticle states, it is likely that quantum theory and its alternatives can be tested for increasingly macroscopic systems Marshall et al., 2003 using the EPR paradox. 

A degenerate waveguide technique, together with a beam splitter, was recently used to demonstrate pulsed entanglement using a traveling-wave OPA Zhang et al., 2007 . 

One might expect that since spin-squeezed and entangled atomic ensembles contain a large number N of atoms, the decoherence rate of such systems would scale as N , where is the single-atom decay rate. 

a critical feature of these collective spin states is that excitation due to interaction with light is distributed symmetrically amongst all of the atoms. 

A well-accepted measure of teleportation efficacy is the overlap of the wave function of the output state with the original input state. 

Since the set of predicted distributions are the conditionals P x xB , one for each value of xB, the logical choice is to label the element of reality by the outcomes xB, but bearing in mind the set of predetermined results is not the set xB , but is the set of associated conditional distributions P x xB . 

For a Gaussian distribution of coherent states, with mean photon number n̄, the average fidelity using classical measure and regenerate strategies is limited to F n̄+1 / 2n̄+1 

The quantum noise properties were characterized at a specific Fourier component within a narrow frequency band, typically in the range 100–300 kHz. 

The first experimental realization of pulsed EPR entanglement, shown in Fig. 7, was based on the approach of mixing two squeezed beams on a 50/50 beam splitteras outlined above for continuous wave light. 

The symmetry of the entangled beams allowed one to infer from this number the degree of EPR violation, which was found to be 2=0.64±0.08. 

These techniques have significant potential for quantum information networks Duan et al., 2001 and are also capable of generating a collective entangled state of the form required to test the EPR paradox. 

The other approach to experimental demonstration of collective spin entanglement in atomic ensembles is to rely on conditioning measurements to prepare the state Julsgaard et al., 2004; Chou et al., 2005 . 

The optimum level of EPR paradox achieved to date was by Bowen, Schnabel, et al. 2003 using a pair of type The authoroptical parametric oscillators. 

The first experimental demonstration of quantum state transfer from the polarization state of an optical field to the collective spin state of an atomic ensemble was performed by Hald et al.