scispace - formally typeset
Open AccessJournal ArticleDOI

Toward a second-person neuroscience.

Reads0
Chats0
TLDR
Evidence from neuroimaging, psychophysiological studies, and related fields are reviewed to argue for the development of a second-person neuroscience, which will help neuroscience to really “go social” and may also be relevant for the understanding of psychiatric disorders construed as disorders of social cognition.
Abstract
In spite of the remarkable progress made in the burgeoning field of social neuroscience, the neural mechanisms that underlie social encounters are only beginning to be studied and could-paradoxically-be seen as representing the "dark matter" of social neuroscience. Recent conceptual and empirical developments consistently indicate the need for investigations that allow the study of real-time social encounters in a truly interactive manner. This suggestion is based on the premise that social cognition is fundamentally different when we are in interaction with others rather than merely observing them. In this article, we outline the theoretical conception of a second-person approach to other minds and review evidence from neuroimaging, psychophysiological studies, and related fields to argue for the development of a second-person neuroscience, which will help neuroscience to really "go social"; this may also be relevant for our understanding of psychiatric disorders construed as disorders of social cognition.

read more

Content maybe subject to copyright    Report

1
To be published in Behavioral and Brain Sciences (in press)
© Cambridge University Press 2012
Below is an unedited, uncorrected BBS Target Article recently accepted for publication. This preprint has
been prepared specifically for potential commentators who wish to nominate themselves for formal
commentary invitation via Editorial Manager: http://bbs.edmgr.com/. The Commentary Proposal
Instructions can be accessed here: http://journals.cambridge.org/BBSJournal/Inst/Call
Please DO NOT write a commentary unless you receive a formal email invitation from the editors. If you
are invited to submit a commentary, a copyedited, corrected version of this paper will be made available.
Toward a second-person neuroscience
Leonhard Schilbach
Bert Timmermans
Vasudevi Reddy
Alan Costall
Gary Bente
Tobias Schlicht
Kai Vogeley
Corresponding author: Leonhard Schilbach, leonhard.schilbach@nf.mpg.de
Max-Planck-Institute for Neurological Research, Cologne, Germany
Abstract: In spite of the remarkable progress made in the burgeoning field of social
neuroscience, the neural mechanisms that underlie social encounters are only beginning to be
studied and could —paradoxically— be seen as representing the ‘dark matter’ of social
neuroscience. Recent conceptual and empirical developments consistently indicate the need for
investigations, which allow the study of real-time social encounters in a truly interactive manner.
This suggestion is based on the premise that social cognition is fundamentally different when we
are in interaction with others rather than merely observing them. In this article, we outline the
theoretical conception of a second-person approach to other minds and review evidence from
neuroimaging, psychophysiological studies and related fields to argue for the development of a
second-person neuroscience, which will help neuroscience to really go social; this may also be
relevant for our understanding of psychiatric disorders construed as disorders of social cognition.
Keywords: mentalizing network; mirror neuron system; social cognition from an interactor's
point of view; social cognition from an observer's point of view; 'problem' of other minds;
second-person neuroscience

2
No more fiendish punishment could be devised, were such thing physically possible, than that one
should be turned loose in society and remain absolutely unnoticed.”
William James (1890), The Principles of Psychology.
1. Introduction
The burgeoning field of social neuroscience has begun to illuminate the complex biological bases
of human social cognitive abilities (Frith & Frith 2010; Ochsner & Lieberman 2001). Many
investigations have focused, in particular, on the neural correlates of our capacity to grasp the
mental states of others. Two neuroanatomically distinct large-scale networks have gained center
stage as the neural substrates of social cognition: the so-called mirror neuron system” (MNS)
and the mentalizing network” (MENT). The former has been taken as evidence for a
simulationist account of social cognition and is believed to give us a first-person grasp” of the
motor goals and intentions of other individuals (Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia 2010). The latter has
been seen as providing evidence for a “Theory Theory” account of social cognition believe to
give us an inferential, reflective (and what might be called a third-person’) grasp of others’
mental states (Frith & Frith 2006, 2010). The apparent disparity between these sets of results
may, however, arise from differences in the experimental paradigms used (cf. Keysers & Gazzola
2007), which run the danger of presupposing the very theoretical frameworks they claim to test.
Consequently, both of these paradigms are investigating actual, but limited domains of social
cognition. Both are, in effect, committed to spectator theories of knowledge. They have focused
on the use of “isolation paradigms” (Becchio et al. 2010), in which participants are required to
merely observe others or think about their mental states rather than participate in social
interaction with them. Consequently, it has remained unclear whether and how activity in the
large-scale neural networks described above is modulated by the degree to which a person does
or does not feel actively involved in an ongoing interaction and whether the networks might
subserve complementary or mutually exclusive roles in this case (Schilbach 2010). After more
than a decade of research, the neural mechanisms underlying social interaction have remained
elusive and could —paradoxically— be seen as representing the ‘dark matter’
1
of social
1
In sensu strictu, the term dark matter is used in physics and astronomy to describe matter, which is inferred
to exist, but which has not been directly observed and may not even be observable. We use the term metaphorically
to denote an important lacuna in current areas of research in social neuroscience, which have been more difficult to
investigate and where, therefore, less is known, but which can at least in principle be explored empirically. To index
this particular usage of the term, ‘dark matter’ is consistently used in inverted commas throughout the paper.

3
neuroscience.
In this target article we propose an approach to the investigation of social cognition focused on
second-person’ engagements. This approach, we argue, will help to throw light on this ‘dark
matter’ and may help social neuroscience to really go social.
1.1 Spectator Theories of Other Minds
Spectatorial accounts of social knowing are not restricted to social neuroscience, but have been
central to the Western intellectual tradition (Dewey 1950). Psychological accounts of how people
make sense of other people have usually shared a common format:
Each is a detached observer, rather than actively engaged with the other in
some joint project.
The information available to each of us about other people is limited and
disorganized, and hence there is a gulf between what we can actually
observe about them, and what they themselves feel, intend, or believe.
Each of us, therefore, has to engage in some or other intellectual ‘detour’
to bridge the gap between what can be immediately experienced about the
other person and that person’s psychological states (see Asch 1952).
As Neisser has pointed out, this detached and intellectualist theoretical approach to how people
make sense of one another has been built into the research which was supposed to support that
very position: namely, people observing video-recordings of other people, and making judgments
of what they saw:
The theories and experiments ... all refer to an essentially passive
onlooker, who sees someone do something (or sees two people do
something) and then makes a judgment about it. He doesn’t mix it up
with the folks he’s watching, never tests his judgments in action or
interaction. He just watches and makes judgments. [...] When people are
genuinely engaged with one another, nobody stops to give grades (Neisser
1980, pp.603-4).

4
Modern cognitive psychology has retained “methodological behaviorism” from precisely the
psychology it claims to have undermined (see Costall 2006; Garner 1999; Jenkins 1986; Leahey
1992; Neisser 1997). According to the textbooks, psychologists in their research necessarily start
from the observation of inherently meaningless, “colorless behavior” (Hull 1943, p.25) and can
only begin to make psychological sense of what they observe on the basis of theorizing. Few
modern psychologists, of course, are Cartesian dualists: they rightly insist that they do not make
an ontological disjunction between behavior and mind.
Nevertheless, psychologists keep framing their methodology, in principle if not in their actual
practice, in the old Hullian, reductionist terms, and hence keep talking themselves into a
methodological dualism of behavior and mind. In so doing, they resurrect for themselves the
traditional dualistic ‘problem’ of other minds. And, when Theory Theorists project this
methodology onto other people and how they make sense of one another, they often enough also
carry the same insoluble problem with them. In relation to the other domains to which it has been
applied, the “Theory Theory” approach has taken for granted that the child has already acquired a
substantial practical understanding of the social domain before attempting to systematize his or
her existing knowledge (such as friction or collisions in the domain of physics, and reproduction
and growth in the domain of biology). This is not the case for “Theory Theory” of Mind (TToM)
in its original form, for, according to TToM, it is only once children have developed a “Theory of
Mind” that they have access to any of the necessary psychological data upon which the theory
could be based.
Of course, “Theory of Mind” does not refer to a theory in the scientific sense, but denotes an
empirical field of study with (apparently) no particular theoretical commitments (cf. Penn &
Povinelli 2008, p.394). Yet to the extent that the most important alternative approach,
“Simulation Theory”, frames the problem of how people make sense of other people in terms of
how psychologists make a detour from the observation of ‘mere’ behavior to psychological states
they both face the same logical impasse. Indeed, there could be no naturally occurring precursors
to “Theory of Mind”, not even evolved ones, if the problem of how we really make sense of one
another is framed in terms of this kind of methodological dualism (see Costall et al. 2006; Leudar
& Costall 2008).

5
1.2 An alternative account of social knowing
Before the rise of recent social cognition research there was already an important body of theory
and research proposing that, typically, when relating to one another, people are not engaged in a
tortuous process of inferences and theorizing about one another, but immediately experience the
other as a subject (see Asch 1952; Heider & Simmel 1944; Runeson & Frykholm 1983; Schutz
1972; Thinès et al. 1991). This approach drew upon Gestalt theory and phenomenology. Here is
Solomon Asch's lucid statement of this position:
The quality of their actions imbues persons with living reality. When we
say that a person is in pain, we see his body as feeling. We do not need to
‘impute’ consciousness to others if we directly perceive the qualities of
consciousness in the qualities of action. Once we see an act that is skillful,
clumsy, alert, or reckless, it is superfluous to go ‘behind’ it to its
conscious substrate, for consciousness has revealed itself in the act (Asch
1952, p.158).
This social perception approach is close to the theoretical perspective we are presenting in this
target article. It is not detached; it is not dispassionate. However, it is, nevertheless, committed to
an observer epistemology, a spectator theory of how we relate to other people. Knowing others is
limited to perceiving them. In this target article, we will be arguing for an approach to social
knowing based on interaction and emotional engagements between people, rather than mere
observation. This second-person approach has already begun to prove productive within
developmental and social psychology and points toward the importance of experiencing and
interacting with others as our primary ways of knowing them (see Section 2 for details). Also,
preliminary evidence from neuroimaging and psychophysiological studies demonstrates profound
differences in neural processing related to the reciprocity of social interaction, which is consistent
with our proposal that the second-person approach can make an important contribution to the
neuroscientific study of social encounters and could, in fact, lead to the development of a second-
person neuroscience (Section 3). In this respect, we provide an outlook for future research by
describing key ideas and objectives of a second-person neuroscience and related objectives in
other areas of research (Section 4). Finally, we argue that the second-person account may also be
relevant for our understanding of psychiatric disorders: While psychiatric disorders such as

Citations
More filters

打磨Using Language,倡导新理念

付伶俐
TL;DR: Using Language部分的�’学模式既不落俗套,又能真正体现新课程标准所倡导的�'学理念,正是年努力探索的问题.
Journal ArticleDOI

An integrated theory of language production and comprehension

TL;DR: It is asserted that producing and understanding are interwoven, and that this interweaving is what enables people to predict themselves and each other.
Journal ArticleDOI

Interpersonal emotion regulation.

TL;DR: This work maps a "space" differentiating classes of interpersonal regulation according to whether an individual uses an interpersonal regulatory episode to alter their own or another person's emotion, and identifies 2 types of processes--response-dependent and response-independent--that could support interpersonal regulation.
Journal ArticleDOI

The present and future use of functional near‐infrared spectroscopy (fNIRS) for cognitive neuroscience

TL;DR: This review aims to provide a comprehensive and state‐of‐the‐art review of fNIRS basics, technical developments, and applications, with a particular focus on neuroimaging in naturalistic environments and social cognitive neuroscience.
References
More filters
Journal ArticleDOI

Intentional relations and social understanding

TL;DR: In this paper, the authors present a four-level framework of social understanding that organizes the ways in which social organisms represent the intentional relations of themselves and other agents, assuming that the information available to an organism about its own intentional relations (or first person information) is qualitatively different from the information known to that organism about other agents' intentional relations, or third person information).
Journal ArticleDOI

Social Feedback to Infants' Babbling Facilitates Rapid Phonological Learning

TL;DR: It is reported the first evidence that caregivers'speech to babbling infants provides crucial, real-time guidance to the development of prelinguistic vocalizations.
Journal ArticleDOI

On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a 'theory of mind'

TL;DR: In the present paper, four related and contentious questions head-on are confronted: what exactly would it mean for a non-verbal organism to have an ‘understanding’ or a ‘representation’ of another animal's mental state?
Journal ArticleDOI

Towards a functional neuroanatomy of pleasure and happiness.

TL;DR: Although the neuroscience of happiness is still in its infancy, further advances might be made through mapping overlap between brain networks of hedonic pleasure with others, such as the brain's default network potentially involved in the other happiness ingredient, eudaimonia or life meaning and engagement.
Related Papers (5)
Frequently Asked Questions (2)
Q1. What contributions have the authors mentioned in the paper "Toward a second-person neuroscience" ?

In spite of the remarkable progress made in the burgeoning field of social neuroscience, the neural mechanisms that underlie social encounters are only beginning to be studied and could —paradoxically— be seen as representing the ‘ dark matter ’ of social neuroscience. Recent conceptual and empirical developments consistently indicate the need for investigations, which allow the study of real-time social encounters in a truly interactive manner. In this article, the authors outline the theoretical conception of a second-person approach to other minds and review evidence from neuroimaging, psychophysiological studies and related fields to argue for the development of a second-person neuroscience, which will help neuroscience to really go social ; this may also be relevant for their understanding of psychiatric disorders construed as disorders of social cognition. This suggestion is based on the premise that social cognition is fundamentally different when the authors are in interaction with others rather than merely observing them. 

Finally, the authors address how insights from a second-person account could be put to use in future research using computational neuroscience techniques and in the emerging field of social neuroendocrinology ( see section 4. 3 ). Concerning the second type of studies, the authors suggest that using the established possibility of exploring joint attention in the scanner may help to understand the neural underpinnings of other ( possibly more explicit ) social cognitive tasks: Overall, the next section, therefore, serves to consider potential new avenues that research might take by embracing a second-person approach. Basically the authors see three options to address this within the context of measuring a single brain: ( a ) studies contrasting the information one can obtain when being in interaction with versus observing someone ( learning studies ) ; ( b ) studies contrasting the effects of being in interaction with versus observing someone on subsequent judgments and behavior ( priming studies ) ; ( c ) studies that establish whether they are susceptible to different contextual influences when they are interacting versus observing.